540 lines
37 KiB
Plaintext
540 lines
37 KiB
Plaintext
1
|
||
July 20, 2001; rev. August 16, 2001
|
||
General Covariance, Gauge Theories and the Kretschmann
|
||
Objection.
|
||
Submitted to Symmetry in Physics: New Reflections,
|
||
Katherine Brading and Elena Castellani ( eds), in preparation.
|
||
John D. Norton 1
|
||
Department of History and Philosophy of Science
|
||
University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh PA USA 15260
|
||
jdnorton@pitt.edu
|
||
How can we reconcile two claims that are now both widely accepted:
|
||
Kretschmann's claim that a requirement of general covariance is physically
|
||
vacuous and the standard view that the general covariance of general relativity
|
||
expresses the physically important diffeomorphism gauge freedom of general
|
||
relativity? I urge that both claims can be held without contradiction if we attend
|
||
to the context in which each is made.
|
||
1 I thank Carlo Rovelli, John Earman, Elena Castellani and Chris Martin for their discussion
|
||
and for forcing me to think this through. I am also grateful for discussion by the participants
|
||
in the "International Workshop: General Covariance and Quantum?: Where Do We Stand,"
|
||
Department of Physics, University of Parma, June 21-23, 2001, organized by Massimo Pauri.
|
||
|
||
|
||
2
|
||
1. Introduction
|
||
Two views...
|
||
When Einstein formulated his general theory of relativity, he presented it as the
|
||
culmination of his search for a generally covariant theory. That this was the signal
|
||
achievement of the theory rapidly became the orthodox conception. A dissident view,
|
||
however, tracing back at least to objections raised by Erich Kretschmann in 1917, holds that
|
||
there is no physical content in Einstein's demand for general covariance. That dissident view
|
||
has grown into the mainstream. Many accounts of general relativity no longer even mention
|
||
a principle or requirement of general covariance.
|
||
What is unsettling for this shift in opinion is the newer characterization of general
|
||
relativity as a gauge theory of gravitation, with general covariance expressing a gauge
|
||
freedom. The recognition of this gauge freedom has proven central to the physical
|
||
interpretation of the theory. That freedom precludes certain otherwise natural sorts of
|
||
background spacetimes; it complicates identification of the theory's observables, since they
|
||
must be gauge invariant; and it is now recognized as presenting special problems for the
|
||
project of quantizing of gravitation.
|
||
...That We Need not Choose Between
|
||
It would seem unavoidable that we can choose at most one of these two views: the
|
||
vacuity of a requirement of general covariance or the central importance of general
|
||
covariance as a gauge freedom of general relativity. I will urge here that this is not so; we
|
||
may choose both, once we recognize the differing contexts in which they arise. Kretschmann's
|
||
claim of vacuity arises when we have some body of physical fact to represent and we are
|
||
given free reign in devising the formalism that will capture it. He urges, correctly I believe,
|
||
that we will always succeed in finding a generally covariant formulation. Now take a
|
||
different context. The theory—general relativity—is fixed both in its formalism and physical
|
||
|
||
|
||
3
|
||
interpretation. Each formal property of the theory will have some meaning. That holds for its
|
||
general covariance which turns out to express an important gauge freedom.
|
||
To Come
|
||
In Section 4 I will lay out this reconciliation in greater detail. As preparation, in
|
||
Sections 2 and 3, I will briefly review the two viewpoints. Finally in Section 5 I will relate the
|
||
reconciliation to the fertile "gauge principle" used in recent particle physics. An Appendix
|
||
discusses the difficulty of making good on Kretschmann's claim that generally covariant
|
||
reformulations are possible for any spacetime theory.
|
||
2. Einstein and Kretschmann's Objection
|
||
Einstein...
|
||
In November 1915 an exhausted and exhilarated Einstein presented the
|
||
gravitational field equations of his general theory of relativity to the Prussian Academy of
|
||
Science. These equations were generally covariant; they retained their form under arbitrary
|
||
transformation of the spacetime coordinate system. This event marked the end of a seven
|
||
year quest, with the final three years of greatest intensity, as Einstein struggled to see that a
|
||
generally covariant theory was physically admissible. 2
|
||
Einstein had several bases for general covariance. He believed that the general
|
||
covariance of his theory embodied an extension of the principle of relativity to acceleration.
|
||
This conclusion seemed automatic to Einstein, just as the Lorentz covariance of his 1905
|
||
formulation of special relativity expressed its satisfaction of the principle of relativity of
|
||
2 Over the last two decades there has been extensive historical work on this episode. Earlier
|
||
works include Stachel (1980) and Norton (1984); the definitive work will be Renn et al. (in
|
||
preparation).
|
||
|
||
|
||
4
|
||
inertial motion. 3 He also advanced what we now call the "point-coincidence" argument. The
|
||
physical content of a theory is exhausted by a catalog of coincidences, such as the coincidence
|
||
of a pointer with a scale, or, if the world consisted of nothing but particles in motion, the
|
||
meetings of their worldlines. These coincidences are preserved under arbitrary coordinate
|
||
transformations; all we do in the transformations is relabel the spacetime coordinates
|
||
assigned to each coincidence. Therefore a physical theory should be generally covariant. Any
|
||
less covariance restricts our freedom to relabel the spacetime coordinates of the coincidences
|
||
and that restriction can be based in no physical fact.
|
||
...and Kretschmann
|
||
Shortly after, Erich Kretschmann (1917) announced that Einstein had profoundly
|
||
mistaken the character of his achievement. In demanding general covariance, Kretschmann
|
||
asserted, Einstein had placed no constraint on the physical content of his theory. He had
|
||
merely challenged his mathematical ingenuity. For, Kretschmann urged, any spacetime
|
||
theory could be given a generally covariant formulation as long as we are prepared to put
|
||
sufficient energy into the task of reformulating it. In arriving at general relativity, Einstein
|
||
had used the "absolute differential calculus" of Ricci and Levi-Civita (now called "tensor
|
||
calculus.") Kretschmann pointed to this calculus as a tool that made the task of finding
|
||
generally covariant formulations of theories tractable. 4
|
||
Kretschmann's argument was slightly more subtle than the above remarks.
|
||
Kretschmann actually embraced Einstein's point-coincidence argument and turned it to his
|
||
own ends. In his objection, he agreed that the physical content of spacetime theories is
|
||
3 The analogy proved difficult to sustain and has been the subject of extensive debate. See
|
||
Norton (1993).
|
||
4 For further discussion of Kretschmann's objection, Einstein's response and of the still active
|
||
debate that follows, see Norton (1993) and Rynasiewicz (1999)
|
||
|
||
|
||
5
|
||
exhausted by the catalog of spacetime coincidences; this is no peculiarity of general
|
||
relativity. For this very reason all spacetime theories can be given generally covariant
|
||
formulations. 5
|
||
Kretschmann's objection doe s seem sustainable. For example, using Ricci and Levi
|
||
Civita's methods it is quite easy to give special relativity a generally covariant formulation.
|
||
In its standard Lorentz covariant formulation, using the standard spacetime coordinates (t,
|
||
x, y, z), special relativity is the theory of a Minkowski spacetime whose geometry is given by
|
||
the invariant line element
|
||
ds2 = c 2dt2 - dx2 -dy2 - dz2 (1)
|
||
Free fall trajectories (and other "straights" of the geometry) are given by
|
||
d2x/dt2 = d2y/dt2 = d2z/dt2 = 0 (2)
|
||
We introduce arbitrary spacetime coordinates x i, for i = 0,...,3 and the invariant line element
|
||
becomes
|
||
ds2 = gik dxi dxk (3a)
|
||
where the matrix of coefficients g ik is subject to a field equation
|
||
Riklm = 0 (3a)
|
||
with Riklm the Riemann-Christoffel curvature tensor. The free falls are now governed by
|
||
d2xi/ds2 + {kim} dxk/ds dxm/ds = 0 (4)
|
||
where {kim} are the Christoffel symbols of the second kind.
|
||
5 Rhetorically, Kretschmann's argument was brilliant. To deny it, Einstein may need to deny
|
||
his own point-coincidence argument. However a persistent ambiguity remains in Einstein's
|
||
original argument. Just what is a point-coincidence? Einstein gives no general definition. He
|
||
gives only a list of illustrations and many pitfalls await those who want to make the
|
||
argument more precise. For example, see Howard (1999).
|
||
|
||
|
||
6
|
||
Examples such as this suggest that Kretschmann was right to urge that generally
|
||
covariant reformulations are possible for all spacetime theories. While the suggestion is
|
||
plausible it is certainly not proven by the examples and any final decision must await
|
||
clarification of some ambiguities. See Appendix 1: Is a Generally Covariant Reformulation
|
||
Always Possible? for further discussion.
|
||
3. The Gauge Freedom of General Relativity
|
||
Active General Covariance
|
||
Einstein spoke of general covariance as the invariance of form of a theory's equations
|
||
when the spacetime coordinates are transformed. It is usually coupled with a so-called
|
||
"passive" reading of general covariance: if we have some system of fields, we can change our
|
||
spacetime coordinate system as we please and the new descriptions of the fields in the new
|
||
coordinate systems will still solve the theory's equations. Einstein's form invariance of the
|
||
theory's equations also licenses a second version, the so-called "active" general covariance. It
|
||
involves no transformation of the spacetime coordinate system. Rather active general
|
||
covariance licenses the generation of many new solutions of the equations of the theory in the
|
||
same coordinate system once one solution has been given.
|
||
For example, assume the equations of some generally covariant theory admit a scalar
|
||
field φ(xi) as a solution. Then general covariance allows us to generate arbitrarily many more
|
||
solutions by, metaphorically speaking, spreading the scalar field differently over the
|
||
spacetime manifold of events. We need a smooth mapping on the events—a
|
||
diffeomorphism—to effect the redistribution. For example, assume we have such a map that
|
||
sends the event at coordinate x i to the event at coordinate x' i in the same coordinate system.
|
||
Such a map might be a uniform doubling, so that x i is mapped to x' i = 2. xi. To define the
|
||
redistributed field φ', we assign to the event at x' i the value of the original field φ at the event
|
||
|
||
|
||
7
|
||
with coordinate x i.6 If the field is not a scalar field, the transformation rule is slightly more
|
||
complicated. For further details of the scalar case, see Appendix 2: From Passive to Active
|
||
Covariance.
|
||
Why it is a Gauge Freedom
|
||
The fields φ(xi) and φ'(xi) are mathematically distinct. But do they represent
|
||
physically distinct fields? The standard view is to assume that they do not, so that they are
|
||
related by a gauge transformation, that is, one that relates mathematically distinct
|
||
representations of the same physical reality. That this is so cannot be decided purely by the
|
||
mathematics. It is a matter of physics and must be settled by physical argumentation.
|
||
A vivid way to lay out the physical arguments is through Einstein's "hole
|
||
argument."7 The transformation on the manifold of events can be set up so that it is the
|
||
identity everywhere outside some nominated neighborhood of spacetime ("the hole") and
|
||
comes smoothly to differ within. We now use the transformation to duplicate
|
||
diffeomorphically all the fields of some generally covariant theory. Do the new fields
|
||
represent the same physical reality as the old? It would be very odd if they did not. Both
|
||
systems of fields agree completely in all invariants; they are just spread differently on the
|
||
manifold. Since observables are given by invariants, they agree in everything observable.
|
||
Moreover, the two systems of field will agree everywhere outside the hole, but they differ
|
||
only within. This means that, in a generally covariant theory, fixing all fields outside this
|
||
neighbor fails to fix the fields within. This is a violation of determinism. In short, if we
|
||
assume the two systems of fields differ in some physical way we must insist upon a difference
|
||
6 To visualize this redistribution in the two dimensional case, imagine that the original field
|
||
is represented by numbers written on a flat rubber membrane. If we now uniformly stretch
|
||
the rubber membrane so it doubles in size, we have the new field.
|
||
7 See Earman and Norton (1987), Norton (1999).
|
||
|
||
|
||
8
|
||
that transcends both observation and the determining power of the theory. The ready
|
||
solution is that these differences are purely ones of mathematical representation and that
|
||
the two systems of fields represent the same physical reality.
|
||
Its Physical Consequences
|
||
Accepting that this gauge freedom has important consequences for the physical
|
||
interpretation of a theory such as general relativity. 8 The theory is developed by positing a
|
||
manifold of spacetime events which is then endowed with metric properties by means of a
|
||
metric tensor field g ik. The natural default is to take the manifold of events as supplying
|
||
some kind of independent background spacetime in which physical processes can unfold. The
|
||
gauge freedom makes it very difficult to retain this view. For, when we apply a
|
||
diffeomorphism to the field and spread the metrical properties differently over events, the
|
||
transformation is purely gauge and we end up changing nothing physical. So now the same
|
||
events are endowed with different properties, yet nothing physical has changed. The simplest
|
||
and perhaps only way to make sense of this is to give up the idea of an independent existence
|
||
of the events of the manifold. In so far as we can associate an event of the manifold with real
|
||
events in the world, that association must change in concert with our redistribution of the
|
||
metrical field over the manifold.
|
||
Our notion of what is observable is affected by similar considerations. What is
|
||
observable is a subset of the physically real and that in turn is expressed by the invariants of
|
||
a theory. Might an observable result consist of the assertion that an invariant of some field
|
||
has such and such a value at some event of the manifold? No. The invariance must also
|
||
include invariance under the gauge transformation and the assertion would fail to be
|
||
invariant under the gauge transformation. In redistributing the fields, the transformation
|
||
8 For further discussion of these and related issues and their import for the quantization of
|
||
gravity see Rovelli (1997).
|
||
|
||
|
||
9
|
||
might relocate that invariant with that value at quite another event of the manifold. If some
|
||
result is eradicated by a gauge transformation, it cannot have been a result expressing
|
||
physical fact since the gauge transformation alters nothing physical. We must resort to more
|
||
refined ways of representing observables. For example, they may be expressed by an
|
||
assertion that two invariants are equal. The event at which the equality resided may vary
|
||
under gauge transformation; but the transformation will preserve the equality asserted.
|
||
4. Reconciliation
|
||
The Context in which Kretschmann's Objection Succeeds
|
||
Kretschmann's objection s ucceeds because he allows us every freedom in
|
||
reformulating and reinterpreting terms within a theory. Thus we easily transformed special
|
||
relativity from its Lorentz covariant formulation (1), (2) to a generally covariant formulation
|
||
(3a), (3b), (4). In doing so, we introduced new variables not originally present. The are the
|
||
coefficients of the metric tensor g ik and the Christoffel symbols { kim}.
|
||
With this amount of freedom, it is plausible that we can arrive at formulations of any
|
||
theory that have any designated formal property. 9 Imagine, for example, that we wanted a
|
||
9 I am distinguishing the formalism of the theory (and its formal properties) from its
|
||
interpretation. The formalism of a theory would be the actual words used, if the theory
|
||
consisted of an English language description, independently of their meanings. Formal
|
||
properties would include such things as the choice of English and the number of words. More
|
||
commonly physical theories use mathematical structures in place of words. These structures
|
||
can be considered quite independently of what we take them to represent in the world. The
|
||
properties we then consider are the purely formal properties. A real valued field on some
|
||
manifold is just a mathematical structure until we specify what it may represent in the
|
||
world. That specification is the job of the interpretation. See next footnote.
|
||
|
||
|
||
10
|
||
formulation of Newtonian particle mechanics in which the string of symbols " E=mc2"
|
||
appears. (This is a purely formal property since we place no conditions on what the string
|
||
might mean.) Here is one way we can generate it. We take the usual expression for the
|
||
kinetic energy K of a particle of mass m moving at velocity v, K=(1/2) mv2. We introduce a
|
||
new quantity E, defined by E = 2K, and also a new label "c" for velocity v, so that c=v. Once
|
||
we substitute these new variables into the expression for kinetic energy, our reformulated
|
||
theory contains the string " E=mc2".
|
||
The physical vacuity arises because we are demanding the formal property of general
|
||
covariance (or some other formal property) without placing further restrictions that would
|
||
preclude it always being achievable. The vacuity would persist even if we demanded a fixed
|
||
physical content; we must simply be careful not to alter our initial physical content as we
|
||
adjust its formal clothing. In the case of the discovery of general relativity, Einstein did not
|
||
keep the physical content fixed. It became fully fixed only after he found a generally
|
||
covariant formulation that satisfied a number of restrictive physical limitation.
|
||
The Context in Which the Diffeomorphism Gauge Freedom has Physical Content
|
||
Matters are quite different if we fix the formalism of the theory and its
|
||
interpretation. So we might be given general relativity in its standard interpretation. 10 If a
|
||
theory has any content at all, we must be able to ascribe some physical meaning to its
|
||
assertions. A fortiori there must some physical meaning in the general covariance of general
|
||
10 By "interpretation" I just mean the rules that tell us how to connect the various terms or
|
||
mathematical structures of the theory with things in the physical world. These rules can
|
||
vary from formulation to formulations and theory to theory. So, in ordinary formulations of
|
||
special relativity, "c" refers to the speed of light. In thermodynamics "c" would refer to
|
||
specific heat.
|
||
|
||
|
||
11
|
||
relativity. It may be trivial or it may not. 11 Consulting the theory, as we did in Section 2
|
||
above reveals that the content is not trivial.
|
||
Things are just the same in our toy example of forcing the string " E=mc2" into a
|
||
formulation of Newtonian particle mechanics. Let us fix the formulation to be the doctored
|
||
one above. We had forced the string " E=mc2" into it. But now that we have done it, the string
|
||
uses symbols that have a meaning and, when we decode what it says about them, we
|
||
discover that the string expresses something physical, the original statement that kinetic
|
||
energy is half mass x (velocity) 2. Mimicking Kretschmann, we would insist that, given
|
||
Newtonian particle mechanics or any other theory, some reformulation with the string is
|
||
assuredly possible; so the demand for it places no restriction on the physically possible. But,
|
||
once we have the reformulation, that string will express something.
|
||
The analogous circumstance arises in the generally covariant reformulation of special
|
||
relativity. The existence of the reformulation is assured. Once we have it, its general
|
||
covariance does express something. In this case, it is a gauge freedom of the geometric
|
||
structure just like that of general relativity. The Lorentz covariant formulation of (1) and (2)
|
||
admits preferred coordinate systems. In effect, some of the physical content of the theory is
|
||
encoded in them. They specify, for example, which are the inertial motions; a body moves
|
||
inertially only if there is a coordinate system in which its spatial coordinates do not change
|
||
with the time coordinate. In the transition to the generally covariant formulation, this
|
||
11 Indeed the assertion may prove to be a logical truth, that is, it would be true by the
|
||
definition of the terms it invokes or it may amount to the definition of term.While their truth
|
||
is assured, such assertions need not be trivial. For example in a formulation of special
|
||
relativity we may assert that that coefficients of the metric tensor are linear functions of the
|
||
coordinates. This turns out to place no physical restriction on the theory; it merely restricts
|
||
us to particular coordinate systems. It is what is known as a coordinate condition that
|
||
defines the restricted class of coordinate systems in which the formulation holds.
|
||
|
||
|
||
12
|
||
content is stripped out of the coordinate systems. We can no longer use constancy of spatial
|
||
coordinates to discern which points move inertially. This content is relocated in the
|
||
Christoffel symbols, which, via equation (4) determine whether a particular motion is
|
||
inertial. The general covariance of (3a), (3b) and (4) leave a gauge freedom in how the metric
|
||
gik and the Christoffel symbols { kim} may be spread over some coordinate system. In one
|
||
coordinate system, they may be spread in many mathematically distinct but physically
|
||
equivalent ways.
|
||
To summarize
|
||
There is no restriction on physical content in saying that there exists a formulation of the
|
||
theory that has some formal property (general covariance, the presence of the string of
|
||
symbols " E=mc2", etc.) But once we fix a particular formulation and interpretation, that very
|
||
same formal property will express something physical, although there is no assurance that it
|
||
will be something interesting.
|
||
5. Gauge Theories in Particle Physics
|
||
This summary generates a new puzzle. One of the most fertile strategies in recent
|
||
decades in particle physics has been to extend the gauge symmetries of non-interacting
|
||
particles and thereby infer to new gauge fields that mediate the interaction between the
|
||
particles. Most simply, the electromagnetic field can be generated as the gauge field that
|
||
mediates interactions of electrons. This power has earned the strategy the label of the "gauge
|
||
principle." How can this strategy succeed if Kretschmann is right and there is no physical
|
||
content in our being able to arrive at a reformulation of expanded covariance? In the particle
|
||
context, this corresponds to a reformulation of expanded gauge freedom. So why doesn't
|
||
Kretschmann's objection also tell us that the strategy of the gauge principle is physically
|
||
vacuous?
|
||
|
||
|
||
13
|
||
The solution lies in the essential antecedent condition of Kretschmann's objection.
|
||
The physical vacuity arises since there are no restrictions placed how we might reformulate a
|
||
theory in seeking generally covariance. It has long been recognized that the assured
|
||
achievement of general covariance can be blocked by some sort of additional restriction on
|
||
how the reformulation may be achieved. Many additional conditions have been suggested,
|
||
including demands for simplicity and restrictions on which extra variables may introduced.
|
||
(For a survey, see Norton, 1993, Section 5; Norton, 1995, Section 4.) The analogous solution
|
||
is what gives the gauge principle its content. In generating gauge fields, we are most
|
||
definitely not at liberty to expand the gauge freedom of some non-interacting particle field in
|
||
any way we please. There is a quite precise recipe that must be followed: we must promote a
|
||
global symmetry of the original particle field to a local symmetry, using the exemplar of the
|
||
electron and the Maxwell field, and the new field arises from the connection introduced to
|
||
preserve gauge equivalence. 12
|
||
There is considerably more that should be said about the details of the recipe and the
|
||
way in which new physical content arises. The recipe is standardly presented as merely
|
||
expanding the gauge freedom of the non-interacting particles, which should mean that the
|
||
realm of physical possibility is unaltered; we merely have more gauge equivalent
|
||
representations of the same physical situations. So how can physically new particle fields
|
||
12 The transition from special relativity in (1) and (2) to the generally covariant formulation
|
||
(3a), (3b) and (4) can be extended by one step. We replace the flatness condition (3a) by a
|
||
weaker condition, a natural relaxation, R ik = glmRilmk = 0. The result is general relativity in
|
||
the source free case. Arbitrary, source free gravitational fields now appear in the generalized
|
||
connection { kim}. We have what amounts to the earliest example of the use of the gauge
|
||
recipe to generate new fields. The analogy to more traditional examples in particle physics is
|
||
obvious.
|
||
|
||
|
||
14
|
||
emerge? This question is currently under detailed and profitable scrutiny. See Martin (2000),
|
||
(manuscript) and contributions to this volume.
|
||
Appendix 1: Is a Generally Covariant Reformulation Always
|
||
Possible?
|
||
As Earman (manuscript, Section 3) has pointed out, it is not entirely clear whether a
|
||
generally covariant reformation is always possible for any spacetime theory. The problem lies
|
||
in ambiguities in the question. Just what counts as "any" spacetime theory? Just what are
|
||
we expecting from a generally covariant reformulation? Let me rehearse some of the
|
||
difficulties and suggest that for most reasonable answers to these questions generally
|
||
covariant reformulation will be possible though not necessarily pretty.
|
||
The Substitution Trick...
|
||
Let us imagine that we are given a spacetime theory in a formulation of restricted
|
||
covariance. It is given in just one spacetime coordinate systems X i. Let us imagine that the
|
||
laws of the theory happen to be given by n equations in the 2n quantities A k, Bk
|
||
Ak(X i) = Bk(X i) (5)
|
||
where k = 1, ..., n and the A k and Bk are functions of the coordinates as indicated. Consider
|
||
an arbitrary coordinate system x i to which we transform by means of the transformation law
|
||
xi = xi(X m) (6)
|
||
We can replace the n equations (5) by equations that hold in the arbitrary coordinate system
|
||
by the simple expedient of inverting the transformation of (6) to recover the expression for
|
||
the X m as a function of the x i, that is X m = X m(xi). Substituting these expressions for X m into
|
||
(5), we recover a version of (5) that holds in the arbitrary coordinate system
|
||
Ak(X i(xm)) = Bk(X i(xm)) (5a)
|
||
|
||
|
||
15
|
||
We seemed to have achieved a generally covariant reformulation of (5) by the most direct
|
||
application of the intuition that coordinate systems are merely labels and we can relabel
|
||
spacetime events as we please.
|
||
...Yields Geometric Objects
|
||
While (5a) is generally covariant, we may not be happy with the form of the general
|
||
covariance achieved—one of the ambiguities mentioned above. We might, as Earman
|
||
(manuscript, Section 3) suggests, want to demand that (5a) be expressed in terms of
|
||
geometric object fields. The standard definition of a geometric object field is that it is an n
|
||
tuple valued field of components on the manifold, with one field for each coordinate system,
|
||
and that the transformation rule that associates the components of different coordinate
|
||
systems have the usual group properties.
|
||
While this definition may appear demanding, it turns out to be sufficiently
|
||
permissive to characterize each side of (5a) as a geometric object field. For example, in each
|
||
coordinate system x m, the geometric object field A has components A k(X i(xm)), which I now
|
||
write as Ak(xm). The transformation rule between the components is induced by the rule for
|
||
coordinate transformations. That is, under the transformation x m to yr(xm), Ak(xm)
|
||
transforms to A k(xm(yr)), where xm(yr) is the inverse of the coordinate transformation. With
|
||
this definition of the transformation law for A k, the components will inherit as much group
|
||
structure as the coordinate transformations themselves have; that is, it will be as much of a
|
||
geometric object field as we can demand. 13 For example, assume the transformations of
|
||
13 Why the hedged "as much group structure as the coordinate transformations themselves
|
||
have"? These general coordinate transformations may not have all the group properties if the
|
||
domains and ranges of the transformations do not match up well. Assume T 1 maps
|
||
coordinates x i on a neighborhood A to coordinates y i on a neighborhood B that is a proper
|
||
subset of A and T 2 maps coordinates y i on B to coordinates z i on A. Then the composition
|
||
|
||
|
||
16
|
||
coordinate systems z p to yr and yr to xm conform to transitivity. Then this same transitivity
|
||
will be inherited by A. We will have A k(xm(zp)) = A k(xm(yr(zp))) since the transitivity of the
|
||
coordinate transformation yields x m(zp) = xm(yr(zp)).
|
||
But areThey the Geometric Objects We Expect?
|
||
While the components A k turn out to be geometric object fields, they are probably not
|
||
the ones we expected. In brief, the reason is that the transformation rule induced by the
|
||
substitution trick does not allow any mixing of the components. That precludes it yielding
|
||
vectors or tensor or like structures; it turns everything into scalar fields. To see how odd this
|
||
is, take a very simple case. Imagine that we have special relativity restricted to just one
|
||
coordinate system X i. Our law might be the law governing the motion of a body of unit mass,
|
||
Fi = A i, where Fi is the four force and A i the four acceleration. Under a Lorentz
|
||
transformation
|
||
Y0 = γ(X 0 – vX 1) Y1 = γ(X 1 – vX 0) Y3 = X 3 Y4 = X 4
|
||
with velocity v in the X 1 direction, c=1 and γ = (1-v2)-1/2.The usual Lorentz transformation for
|
||
the components A i of the four acceleration would be
|
||
A' 0 = γ(A 0 – vA1) A' 1 = γ(A 1 – vA0) A' 3 = A 3 A' 4 = A 4 (6)
|
||
Note that the transformed A' 0 and A' 1 are linear sums of terms in A 0 and A1. For this same
|
||
transformation, the substitution trick merely gives us
|
||
A' i = A i(X m(Yr)) (6a)
|
||
That is, A' 0 is a function of A 0 only and A' 1 is a function of A 1 only.
|
||
This oddity becomes a disaste r if we apply the substitution rule in a natural way.
|
||
Instead of starting with Ai in one fixed coordinate system X i, we might start will the full set
|
||
T2T1 cannot coincide with the direct transformation of x i to zi since the composition has lost
|
||
that part of the transformation outside B.
|
||
|
||
|
||
17
|
||
of all components of A i in all coordinate systems related by a Lorentz transformation to X i. If
|
||
we now try and make this bigger object generally covariant by the substitution trick, we will
|
||
end up with two incompatible transformation laws for the transformation X i to Yi when we
|
||
try to transform the components A i—the law (6) and law (6a). We no longer have a geometric
|
||
object field since we no longer have a unique transformation law for the components.
|
||
The escape from this last problem is to separate the two transformation groups. We
|
||
consider A i in coordinate system X i and A' i in coordinate system Y i separately and convert
|
||
them into distinct geometric object fields by the substitution trick. As geometric object fields
|
||
they have become, in effect, scalar fields. The Lorentz transformation then reappears as a
|
||
transformation between these geometric objects.
|
||
The Coordinates as Scalars Trick
|
||
If this is our final goal, then another general trick for generating generally covariant
|
||
reformulations could have gotten us there much faster. We return to A k(X i) of (5). We can
|
||
conceive the X i as scalar fields on the manifold—that is really all they are. 14 Scalar fields are
|
||
geometric object fields already. The A i are functions of X i, that is, functions of scalar fields.
|
||
Therefore they are also geometric objects. So we can conceive of the entire structure A k(X i) as
|
||
a geometric object field. We have gotten general covariance on the cheap. We cannot avoid a
|
||
cost elsewhere in the theory however. Our reformulation is overloaded with structure, one
|
||
geometric object field for each of what was originally a component. There is clearly far more
|
||
mathematical structure present than has physical significance. So the theory will need a
|
||
careful system for discerning just which parts of all this structure has physical significance.
|
||
14 Ask, what is the X 0 coordinate in coordinate system X i of some event p? The answer will be
|
||
the same number if we ask it from any other coordinate system y i as long as we are careful to
|
||
ask it of the original coordinate system X i. That is, each coordinate can be treated as a scalar
|
||
field.
|
||
|
||
|
||
18
|
||
Temptations Resisted
|
||
These devices for inducing general covarianc e are clumsy but they do fall within the
|
||
few rules discussed. We might be tempted to demand that we only admit generally covariant
|
||
formulations if their various parts fall together into nice compact geometric objects. But what
|
||
basis do we have for demanding this? Are we to preclude the possibility that the theory we
|
||
started with is just a complicated mess that can only admit an even more complicated mess
|
||
when given generally covariant reformulations. (Newtonian theory has been accused of this!)
|
||
And if we are to demand only nice and elegant reformulations, just how do we define "nice
|
||
and elegant"?
|
||
My conclusion is that generally covariant reformulations are possible under the few
|
||
rules discussed and that efforts to impose further rules to block the more clumsy ones will
|
||
cause more trouble than they are worth elsewhere.
|
||
Appendix 2: From Passive to Active Covariance
|
||
As above, assume the equations of some generally covariant theory admit a scalar
|
||
field φ(xi) as a solution. We can transform to a new coordinate system by merely relabeling
|
||
the events of spacetime; x i is relabeled x' i, where the x'i are smooth functions of the x i. The
|
||
field φ(xi) transforms to field φ'(x'i) by the simple rule φ'(x'i) = φ(xi). Since the equations of the
|
||
theory hold in the new coordinate system, the new field φ'(x'i) will still be a solution. The two
|
||
fields φ(xi) and φ'(x'i) are just representations of the same physical field in different
|
||
spacetime coordinate systems.
|
||
This is the passive view of general covariance. It can be readily t ransmogrified into
|
||
an active view, a transition that Einstein had already undertaken with his 1914 statements
|
||
of the "hole argument". What makes φ'(x'i) a solution of the theory under discussion is
|
||
nothing special about the coordinate system x' i. It is merely the particular function that φ'
|
||
happens to be. It is a function that happens to satisfy the equations of the theory. We could
|
||
|
||
|
||
19
|
||
take that very same function and use it in the original coordinate system, x i. That is, we
|
||
could form a new field φ'(xi). Since this new field uses the very same function, it retains every
|
||
property except the mention of the primed coordinate system x' i. Thus it is also a solution of
|
||
the equations of the theory.
|
||
In short, the passive general covariance of the theory has delivered us two fields,
|
||
φ(xi) and φ'(xi). They are not merely two representations of the same field in different
|
||
coordinate systems. They are defined in the same coordinate system and are mathematically
|
||
distinct fields, in so far as their values at given events will (in general) be different. Active
|
||
general covariance allows the generation of the field φ'(xi) from φ(xi) by the transformation xi
|
||
to x'i.
|
||
References
|
||
Earman, John (manuscript) "Once More General Covariance."
|
||
Earman, John and Norton, John D. (1987): "What Price Spacetime Substantivalism? The
|
||
Hole Argument," British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 38, pp. 515-25.
|
||
Howard, Don (1999) "Point Coincidences and Pointer Coincidences: Einstein on the Invariant
|
||
Content of Space-Time Theories," in H. Goenner, J. Renn, J. Ritter, T. Sauer (eds.)
|
||
The Expanding Worlds of General Relativity (Einstein Studies volume 7) pp. 463
|
||
500.
|
||
Kretschmann, Erich (1917): "Über den physikalischen Sinn der Relativitätspostulat, A
|
||
Einsteins neue und seine ursprünglische Relativitätstheorie," Annalen der Physik,
|
||
53, 575-614.
|
||
Martin, Christopher (2000) "The Gauge Argument," Talk at the Philosophy of Science
|
||
Association Biennial Meeting, Vancouver, 2-5, November, 2000.
|
||
Martin, Christopher (manuscript) Dissertation, Department of History and Philosophy of
|
||
Science, University of Pittsburgh.
|
||
|
||
|
||
20
|
||
Norton, John D. (1984) "How Einstein found his Field Equations: 1912-1915," Historical
|
||
Studies in the Physical Sciences, 14, 253-316; reprinted in Don Howard and John
|
||
Stachel (eds.) Einstein and the History of General Relativity: Einstein Studies, Vol.
|
||
1 Boston: Birkhäuser, 1989, pp.101-159.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1993), "General Covariance and the Foundations of General Relativity:
|
||
Eight Decades of Dispute," Reports on Progress in Physics, 56, pp. 791-858.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1995) "Did Einstein Stumble? the Debate Over General Covariance,"
|
||
Erkenntnis 42, pp. 223-45.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1999) "The Hole Argument," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|
||
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spacetime-holearg/
|
||
Renn, Jürgen; Sauer, Tilman; Janssen, Michel; Norton, John D. and Stachel John (in
|
||
preparation) General Relativity in the Making; Einstein's Zurich Notebook.
|
||
Rovelli, Carlo (1997) "Halfway through the Woods: Contemporary Research on Space and
|
||
Time," pp. 180-223 in J. Earman and J. D. Norton (eds.) The Cosmos of Science:
|
||
Essays of Exploration. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
|
||
Rynasiewicz, Robert (1999) "Kretschmann's Analysis of General Covariance and Relativity
|
||
Principles," in H. Goenner, J. Renn, J. Ritter, T. Sauer (eds.) The Expanding
|
||
Worlds of General Relativity (Einstein Studies volume 7) pp. 431-462.
|
||
Stachel, John (1980): "Einstein's Search for General Covariance," paper read at the Ninth
|
||
International Conference on General Relativity and Gravitation, Jena; printed in
|
||
Don Howard and John Stachel (eds.) Einstein and the History of General Relativity:
|
||
Einstein Studies, Vol. 1 (Boston: Birkhäuser, 1989) pp.63-100. |