322 lines
22 KiB
Plaintext
322 lines
22 KiB
Plaintext
1
|
||
July 27, 2001; Revised August 15, 2001
|
||
Einstein's Triumph over the Spacetime Coordinate System:
|
||
A Paper presented in Honor of Roberto Torretti
|
||
John D. Norton1
|
||
Department of History and Philosophy of Science
|
||
University of Pittsburgh
|
||
Pittsburgh PA 15260
|
||
1. Introduction
|
||
Each student of Einstein must eventually make his or her their peace with Einstein's
|
||
pronouncements on relativity and spacetime coordinate systems. Einstein saw the
|
||
development of relativity as the ultimately successful struggle to overcome certain spacetime
|
||
coordinate systems and thereby to implement a generalized principle of relativity. This
|
||
signal achievement of relativity is embodied in its general covariance. We now hold
|
||
spacetime coordinate systems merely to be convenient devices for smoothly labeling events.
|
||
The selection of a coordinate system amounts to little more than a conventional choice of
|
||
1 Dr. Torretti has inspired my generation: in scholarship, by setting the standard in his
|
||
researches in history and philosophy of space and time; and in humanity with his generosity
|
||
and kindness. I take this opportunity to thank him personally for the stimulating model of
|
||
scholarship in his Relativity and Geometry and related writings and for his encouragement,
|
||
patience and instruction when I first worked in history and philosophy of space and time,
|
||
especially during a year we shared at the Center for Philosophy of Science, University of
|
||
Pittsburgh, in 1983-1984. He helped make it one the most exciting years intellectually of my
|
||
life.
|
||
|
||
|
||
2
|
||
numbers, much like the selection of definition. How can one proclaim victory over a
|
||
definition? If we are offended by a definition, the more appropriate attitude is just to decide
|
||
quietly not to use it.
|
||
Dr. Torretti's celebrated Relativity and Geometry and related writings represent a
|
||
landmark of scholarship. They provide our most detailed account of how Einstein's work in
|
||
relativity theory changed physical geometry. It is presented in a comprehensive historical
|
||
context with the uncompromised insistence that every geometric conception must be
|
||
explicated to the highest standards of mathematical rigor. So when Dr. Torretti makes his
|
||
peace with the problem of Einstein and spacetime coordinates in Section 5.5 "General
|
||
Covariance and the Einstein-Grossmann theory," this latter insistence ensures that the
|
||
peace will be uncomfortable—for Einstein. He takes Einstein's formulation of the postulate of
|
||
general covariance and rephrases in language that mimics Einstein's 1905 statement of the
|
||
principle of relativity of special relativity. Calling it the "principle of general relativity," Dr.
|
||
Torretti explains why the similarity of the two relativity principles is only superficial. Unlike
|
||
the case of the special principle, the general principle does not assert a physical equivalence
|
||
of states of motion. Dr. Torretti's analysis is careful, thorough and leaves no room to quibble.
|
||
So we are left with a puzzle. How could Einstein be so confused about the fundamentals of
|
||
his own theory?
|
||
My goal in this paper is small. I do not want to dispute Dr. Torretti's careful analysis.
|
||
Rather I offer an extended footnote to it. I want to try to explain what Einstein intended in
|
||
his remarks about coordinate systems. There is, I believe, a natural reading for Einstein's
|
||
claims that do make perfect sense. They require us to adopt a physical interpretation of
|
||
relativity theory that is now no longer popular, so the natural reading will no longer have
|
||
intrinsic interest. It will, however, allow us to make sense of Einstein's claims and his
|
||
program.
|
||
|
||
|
||
3
|
||
2. "The Vanquishing of the Inertial System"
|
||
A Letter to Besso
|
||
When we face claims that are unintelligible in the writing of an Einstein, we are
|
||
often tempted to dismiss them as remarks made in haste in the frenzied first moments of
|
||
great discovery. Might they not be retracted or qualified in some essential way as time brings
|
||
sober distance from those heady moments? While time mellowed Einstein, we can be sure
|
||
this was not the case with his proclamations over coordinate systems. He brought the general
|
||
theory of relativity to a generally covariant formulation in November 1915. Nearly 40 years
|
||
later, after his theory had been much celebrated and its foundations subject to minute
|
||
scrutiny, Einstein wrote to his lifelong friend and confidant, Michele Besso.
|
||
His letter of August 10, 1954, lays out a brief account of the essence of the general theory of
|
||
relativity, explicitly intended to be free of entanglement with the history of the theory.
|
||
(Speziali, 1972, p.525)2
|
||
Your characterization of the general theory of relat.[ivity] characterizes the
|
||
genetic side quite well. It is also valuable afterwards, however, to analyze the
|
||
whole matter logically-formally. For as long as one cannot determine the
|
||
physical content of the theory on account of temporarily insurmountable
|
||
mathematical difficulties, logical simplicity is the only criterion of the value of
|
||
the theory, even if it is naturally an insufficient one.
|
||
The special th.[eory] of r.[elativity] is really nothing other than an adaptation
|
||
of the idea of the inertial system to the empirically confirmed conviction of the
|
||
constancy of the velocity of light with respect to each inertial system. It does not
|
||
vanquish the epistemologically untenable concept of the inertial system. (The
|
||
2 I thank Karola Stotz for help in this translation.
|
||
|
||
|
||
4
|
||
untenability of this concept was brought to light especially clearly by Mach and
|
||
was, however, already recognized with lesser clarity by Huygens and Leibniz.)
|
||
The core of this objection against Newton's fundamentals is best explained
|
||
through the analogy with the "center point of the world" of Aristotelian physics:
|
||
there is a center point of the world, towards which heavy bodies strive. This
|
||
explains, f[or] e[xample], the spherical shape of the earth. The ugliness in it is
|
||
that this center point of the world acts on all others, but that all these others
|
||
(i.e. bodies) do not act back on the center point of the earth. (One-sided causal
|
||
nexus.)
|
||
It is just like this with inertial systems. They determine the inertial relations
|
||
of things everywhere, without being influenced by them. (Really one ought better
|
||
to speak of the aggregate of all inertial systems; however this is inessential.) The
|
||
essence of the gen.[eral] th.[eory] of rel.[ativity] (G. R.) lies in the vanquishing
|
||
[Ueberwindung] of inertial systems. (This was still not so clear at the time of the
|
||
setting up of G. R., but was subsequently recognized principally through Levi
|
||
Civita.) In the setting up of the theory I had chosen the symmetric tensor gik as
|
||
the starting concept. It provided the possibility of defining the "displacement
|
||
field" Γlik...
|
||
Einstein briefly explained the notion of the displacement field and its independence from the
|
||
metric gik. He continued:
|
||
But how is it that the displacement field really led to the vanquishing of
|
||
inertial systems? If one has vectors with the same components at two arbitrarily
|
||
distant points P and Q in an inertial system, then this is an objective (invariant)
|
||
relation: they are equal and parallel. On this rests the circumstance that one
|
||
obtains tensors again through differentiation of tensors with respect to the
|
||
coordinates in an inertial system and that e.g. the wave equation represents an
|
||
objective expression in inertial systems. The displacement field now allows such
|
||
|
||
|
||
5
|
||
tensor formation by differentiation in relation to an arbitrary coordinate system.
|
||
Therefore it is the invariant substitute of inertial systems and thereby--as it
|
||
appears--the foundation of every relativistic field theory.
|
||
Einstein then continued to explain how the metric and displacement field are used to
|
||
formulate general relativity and his unified field theory.
|
||
Its Unusual Treatment of Coordinate Systems
|
||
Einstein finds the essence of the general theory to lie in the vanquishing of inertial
|
||
systems, that is, inertial coordinate systems. Part of his account is that these systems have
|
||
the objectionable feature of acting without being acted upon. That aspect has been subject to
|
||
much discussion and analysis. It is usually explicated by the notion of "absolute object,"
|
||
geometric objects that act but are not acted upon. In special relativity, the pertinent absolute
|
||
object is the Minkowski metric.3 Here I pass over the problem of explicating the absoluteness
|
||
Einstein raises; I am interested in just one other aspect. Einstein's notion of the absolute
|
||
inertial [coordinate] system has been transmogrified into an absolute geometric object, the
|
||
Minkowski metric.
|
||
It is so tempting to say that this transformation is what Einstein really intended. But
|
||
then we must be amazed at his tenacity in avoiding the assertion. His remarks to Besso
|
||
mention the metric field and the displacement field, both geometric objects, but condemns
|
||
the inertial system for its absolute character—and this forty years after his achievement of
|
||
general covariance.4
|
||
3 For discussion see Norton (1993, Section 8).
|
||
4 Similar remarks on inertial systems span Einstein's life. They appear, for example, as early
|
||
as Einstein (1913, pp. 1260-61) and as late as a letter to George Jaffé of January 19, 1954
|
||
(Einstein Archive, document with duplicate archive control number 13 405).
|
||
|
||
|
||
6
|
||
2. Einstein's use of Coordinate Systems
|
||
Their Physical Content
|
||
There is a simple way to understand Einstein's remarks.5 He did not regard
|
||
coordinate systems as we now do, as essentially arbitrary systems of numerical labels of
|
||
events. In his theorizing, they initially carried significant physical content. The journey to
|
||
the completion of general relativity required the systematic elimination of this content.
|
||
That coordinate systems can be used to represent significant physical content is not
|
||
the modern view and it is tempting to think that no other view is possible. But that
|
||
narrowmindedness is quite incorrect. Our physical theories use mathematical structures to
|
||
represent aspects of interest of the physical world. We routinely use a manifold that is
|
||
topologically R4 to represent the set of physical events in special relativity. Nothing prevents
|
||
us using the structurally richer number manifold of quadruples of reals as this manifold. If
|
||
we do use a number manifold in this way, then we are assigning quadruples of reals to
|
||
events in spacetime. That is just what a coordinate system does.
|
||
A number manifold has considerably more structure than we use in standard
|
||
theories of spacetime. It has a preferred origin (0,0,0,0), for example. How are we to interpret
|
||
that? Does this preferred origin correspond to a real physical center point of the world?
|
||
Whether it does or not cannot be decided purely by the mathematics of the theory. The
|
||
mathematics can only affirm that (0,0,0,0) is indeed different from all other points in R4, but
|
||
not that the differences amount to nothing physically. This last judgment must be made by
|
||
the physical interpretation we supply for the mathematical structures. The modern view is to
|
||
discount it as physically insignificant. Einstein's default was the opposite. The various
|
||
5 I have developed the approach to Einstein's use of coordinate systems sketched below in
|
||
greater detail in Norton (1989, 1992).
|
||
|
||
|
||
7
|
||
features of coordinate systems represent physical features of the world. Most crudely, the
|
||
origin (0,0,0,0) is a physical center point. In Einstein's program, we must find a way of
|
||
depriving coordinate systems of this default physical content.
|
||
...and How it is Systematically Denied
|
||
Einstein used a single technique that was not his own invention. He used a strategy
|
||
codified by Felix Klein in the nineteenth century.6 Each geometric theory would be
|
||
associated with a class of admissible coordinate systems and a group of transformations that
|
||
would carry us between them. The cardinal rule was that physical significance can be
|
||
assigned just to those features that were invariants of this group. In special relativity, that
|
||
group is the Poincaré group. The origin (0,0,0,0) is not an invariant; under translations
|
||
within the group, the origin is not mapped back to itself. Thus it has no physical significance.
|
||
But the light cone structure –the complete catalog of the pairs of events that are lightlike
|
||
separated7—is invariant and thus has physical significance.
|
||
3. The Development of Relativity Theory
|
||
The Default Interpretation of Spacetime Coordinate Systems...
|
||
Einstein's natural starting point is to assign physical significance to the natural
|
||
features of a coordinate system. Using the familiar (t, x, y, z) as the spacetime coordinates,
|
||
we can list some of them:
|
||
6 For a more detailed account of the connection to nineteenth century geometry, see Norton
|
||
(1999).
|
||
7 In coordinate terms, the pair satisfies the condition ∆t2 - ∆x2 - ∆y2 - ∆z2 = 0, where (t, x, y, z)
|
||
are the usual spacetime coordinates, ∆ represents the coordinate differentials and the speed
|
||
of light is set to unity.
|
||
|
||
|
||
8
|
||
(a) The origin (0,0,0,0) corresponds to a central point; the distinction between the x, y and z
|
||
coordinates makes space anisotropic.
|
||
(b) The curves picked out by constant values of x, y and z are a state of rest.
|
||
(c) In a Lorentz or Galilean covariant theory, the set of all curves picked out by (b) for all
|
||
coordinate systems are the inertial states of motion.
|
||
(d) Coordinate differences have metrical significance; they represent the possible results of
|
||
clock and rod measurements by observers in the state of rest picked out by (b).
|
||
...and Their Loss of Physical Significance
|
||
The development of relativity theory brings the systematic elimination of these
|
||
default physical interpretations. As our starting point, we might imagine a one-coordinate
|
||
system theory. It would have all the physical structures of the list above (a)-(e). The first step
|
||
had already been taken in the nineteenth century. The spatial sections of the spacetime are
|
||
covered by coordinates x, y, z. The Euclidean character of space entails that we can use many
|
||
coordinate systems related by translations, rotations and reflections. None of the structures
|
||
of (a) are invariants of these transformations. They lose physical significance.
|
||
The Relativity of Motion
|
||
The theory would retain an absolute state of rest (b), however. That is eliminated by
|
||
the transition to a Newtonian spacetime, with the characteristic group the Galilean group, or
|
||
to special relativity with the characteristic group the Poincaré group. The states of rest (b)
|
||
are no longer invariant.
|
||
|
||
|
||
9
|
||
The next step marks the starting point of Einstein's 1907 quest for his general theory
|
||
of relativity.8 Einstein sought to expand the covariance of his theory further so as to deprive
|
||
the inertial states of motion (c) of physical significance. This, he believed, was achieved with
|
||
his postulation of the principle of equivalence which now allowed him to extend the Poincaré
|
||
group with transformations that represented uniform acceleration, although in only limited
|
||
circumstances. Einstein immediately interpreted the expansion as representing an extension
|
||
of the principle of relativity to acceleration. In this account, we see why: the inertial motions
|
||
of (c) are no longer invariants of the admissible transformations.
|
||
Metrical Significance
|
||
Presumably this much was all Einstein expected in 1907. In 1912, Einstein realized
|
||
that the development of his theory required him to take another step in depriving
|
||
coordinates of physical significance. He saw an analogy between the problem of gravitation
|
||
and relativity and the theory of curved surfaces of Gauss. The latter has led to a new
|
||
mathematics in which one could use arbitrary coordinate systems and in which coordinate
|
||
differences cease to have the direct metrical significance of (d).9
|
||
8 There has been very considerable investigation in recent decades of Einstein's passage to
|
||
the general theory of relativity. They span from early work including Torretti (1983), Norton
|
||
(1984) and Stachel (1980) to Renn (in preparation).
|
||
9 Here I will report Dr. Torretti's repeated lament that the group structure—or lack of it—of
|
||
Einstein's expanded coordinate systems brought many unintended problems apparently
|
||
ignored by Einstein. For example (Torretti, 1983, p. 153) observes that the ranges of two
|
||
coordinate charts may not overlap, so that the point transformation by induced the
|
||
corresponding coordinate transformation may have degenerate properties. Einstein largely
|
||
maintained a physicist's silence on these mathematical niceties.
|
||
|
||
|
||
10
|
||
Independent Existence
|
||
With this development, Einstein's quest for depriving coordinate systems of their
|
||
default physical significance has taken an unanticipated turn. It proved to be a trifle in
|
||
comparison to the final hurdle that Einstein needed to overcome in arriving at a generally
|
||
covariant formulation of his general theory of relativity. Having failed to find what he
|
||
thought were admissible generally covariant gravitational field equations in 1912 and 1913,
|
||
Einstein eventually found a way to discount the failure. He developed arguments that
|
||
purported to show that general covariance would be physically uninteresting, were it to be
|
||
achieved. The best known and most important of these was the "hole argument."
|
||
The error of Einstein's argumentation is now well known. He had generated two
|
||
intertransformable metric fields gik(xm) and g'ik(xm) in the same coordinate system, xm. He
|
||
had assumed that the two fields represented two distinct physical possibilities. That proved
|
||
to be the elusive error that took several years to find. Einstein presumed that it made sense
|
||
to say that the two fields were in the same coordinate system. That tacitly accorded an
|
||
existence to the coordinate system independent of the metric field defined on it. Figuratively,
|
||
it meant that it makes sense to say that we can remove the first field from the coordinate
|
||
system, leave a bare coordinate system behind and then deposit the second fieldin the very
|
||
same coordinate system.
|
||
One of the final stages of Einstein's development of a generally covariant theory was
|
||
to recognize that coordinate systems have no such independent existence. He described his
|
||
error to Besso in a letter of January 3, 1916:10
|
||
10 Schulmann et al. (1998) Papers, Vol. 8A, Doc. 178; Einstein's emphasis. I have argued
|
||
elsewhere that Einstein's according independent reality to coordinate systems may have had
|
||
catastrophic effects at an earlier stage of his quest for general covariance. See "What Was
|
||
Einstein's Fatal Prejudice?" in Renn et al. (in preparation).
|
||
|
||
|
||
11
|
||
There is no physical content in two different solutions G(x) [gik(xm)] and G'(x)
|
||
[g'ik(xm)] existing with respect to the same coordinate system K. To imagine two
|
||
solutions simultaneously in the same manifold has no meaning and the system
|
||
K has no physical reality.
|
||
4. Conclusion
|
||
These considerations, however, have little force with modern readers. We now
|
||
proceed from a quite different starting point. We do not accord default physical significance
|
||
to coordinate systems. If we wish to endow a spacetime with inertial structures, absolute or
|
||
otherwise, we start where Einstein ended. We start by endowing a manifold with an affine
|
||
connection (displacement field) whose natural straights are the inertial motions. In all this,
|
||
coordinate systems are little more than convenient labels for spacetime events.
|
||
For Einstein, however, matters looked quite different. His default was to load
|
||
physical content into the coordinate systems. The conceptual development through special to
|
||
general relativity is characterized by depriving coordinate systems of their default physical
|
||
significance in progressively greater measure. He had initially intended to end up just
|
||
depriving coordinate systems of absolute inertial motions. Once Einstein had started the
|
||
process, it could not be stopped. The natural development of the theory ended up forcing
|
||
much more. The coordinate systems lost their metrical significance and, after much
|
||
suffering, he finally recognized the need to dispense with a notion of independent existence
|
||
he had tacitly accorded them.
|
||
References
|
||
Einstein, Albert (1913a) "Zum gegenwärtigen Stande des Gravitationsproblems,"
|
||
Physikalische Zeitschrift, 14, pp.1249-1262.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1984) "How Einstein found his Field Equations: 1912-1915," Historical
|
||
Studies in the Physical Sciences, 14, 253-316; reprinted in Don Howard and John
|
||
|
||
|
||
12
|
||
Stachel (eds.) Einstein and the History of General Relativity: Einstein Studies, Vol. 1
|
||
Boston: Birkhäuser, 1989, pp.101-159.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1989) "Coordinates and Covariance: Einstein's view of spacetime and the
|
||
modern view," Foundations of Physics, 19, 1215-1263.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1992) "The Physical Content of General Covariance" in J. Eisenstaedt and
|
||
A. Kox eds., Studies in the History of General Relativity: Einstein Studies, Vol.3,
|
||
Boston: Birkhauser.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1993), "General Covariance and the Foundations of General Relativity:
|
||
Eight Decades of Dispute," Reports on Progress in Physics, 56, pp. 791-858.
|
||
Norton, John D. (1999) "Geometries in Collision: Einstein, Klein and Riemann." in J. Gray,
|
||
ed., The Symbolic Universe . Oxford University Press, pp.128-144.
|
||
Renn, Jürgen; Sauer, Tilman; Janssen, Michel; Norton, John D. and Stachel John (in
|
||
preparation) General Relativity in the Making; Einstein's Zurich Notebook.
|
||
Schulmann, Robert; Kox, A. J.; Janssen, Michel; and Illy, József (eds.) (1998) The Collected
|
||
Papers of Albert Einstein. Volume 8. The Berlin Years: Correspondence, 1914-1918.
|
||
Part A: 1914-1917. Part B: 1918. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (“Papers,
|
||
Vol. 8”)
|
||
Speziali, Pierre (ed., trans.) (1972) Albert Einstein Michele Besso: Correspondance 1903-1955.
|
||
Paris: Hermann.
|
||
Stachel, John (1980): "Einstein's Search for General Covariance," paper read at the Ninth
|
||
International Conference on General Relativity and Gravitation, Jena; printed in
|
||
Don Howard and John Stachel (eds.) Einstein and the History of General Relativity:
|
||
Einstein Studies, Vol. 1 (Boston: Birkhäuser, 1989) pp.63-100.
|
||
Torretti, Roberto (1983) Relativity and Geometry. Oxford: Pergamon. |