zotero-db/storage/2HVQHJRD/.zotero-ft-cache

4105 lines
164 KiB
Plaintext
Raw Blame History

This file contains ambiguous Unicode characters

This file contains Unicode characters that might be confused with other characters. If you think that this is intentional, you can safely ignore this warning. Use the Escape button to reveal them.

9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
The Project Gutenberg eBook of Symbolic Logic
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this ebook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this eBook.
Title: Symbolic Logic
Author: Lewis Carroll
Release date: May 5, 2009 [eBook #28696] Most recently updated: January 5, 2021
Language: English
Credits: Produced by Tony Browne, Geetu Melwani, Greg Weeks, L. Lynn Smith and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net
*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK SYMBOLIC LOGIC ***
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
pg_i
By Lewis Carroll
pg_ii
pg_iii
A Syllogism worked out.
pg_iv
That story of yours, about your once meeting the sea-serpent, always sets me off yawning; I never yawn, unless when Im listening to something totally devoid of interest.
The Premisses, separately.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
1/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
The Premisses, combined.
The Conclusion.
That story of yours, about your once meeting the sea-serpent, is totally devoid of interest.
SYMBOLIC LOGIC
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg_v
2/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
PART I
ELEMENTARY
BY
LEWIS CARROLL
SECOND THOUSAND FOURTH EDITION
PRICE TWO SHILLINGS
London MACMILLAN AND CO., Limited new york: the macmillan company
1897
All rights reserved
Richard Clay and Sons, Limited,
pg_vi
london and bungay
ADVERTISEMENT.
pg_vii
An envelope, containing two blank Diagrams (Biliteral and Triliteral) and 9 counters (4 Red and 5 Grey), may be had, from Messrs. Macmillan, for 3d., by post 4d.
I shall be grateful to any Reader of this book who will point out any mistakes or misprints he may happen to notice in it, or any passage which he thinks is not clearly expressed.
I have a quantity of MS. in hand for Parts II and III, and hope to be able——should life, and health, and opportunity, be granted to me, to publish them in the course of the next few years. Their contents will be as follows:—
PART II. ADVANCED.
Further investigations in the subjects of Part I. Propositions of other forms (such as “Not-all x are y”). Triliteral and Multiliteral Propositions (such as “All abc are de”). Hypotheticals. Dilemmas. &c. &c.
Part III. TRANSCENDENTAL.
Analysis of a Proposition into its Elements. Numerical and Geometrical Problems. The Theory of Inference. The Construction of Problems. And many other Curiosa Logica.
PREFACE TO THE FOURTH EDITION.
pg_viii
The chief alterations, since the First Edition, have been made in the Chapter on Classification (pp. 2, 3) and the Book on Propositions (pp. 10 to 19). The chief additions
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
3/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
have been the questions on words and phrases, added to the Examination-Papers at p. 94, and the Notes inserted at pp. 164, 194.
In Book I, Chapter II, I have adopted a new definition of Classification, which enables me to regard the whole Universe as a Class, and thus to dispense with the very awkward phrase a Set of Things.
In the Chapter on Propositions of Existence I have adopted a new normal form, in which the Class, whose existence is affirmed or denied, is regarded as the Predicate, instead of the Subject, of the Proposition, thus evading a very subtle difficulty which besets the other form. These subtle difficulties seem to lie at the root of every Tree of Knowledge, and they are far more hopeless to grapple with than any that occur in its higher branches. For example, the difficulties of the Forty-Seventh Proposition of Euclid are mere childs play compared with the mental torture endured in the effort to think out the essential nature of a straight Line. And, in the present work, the difficulties of the “5 Liars” Problem, at p. 192, are “trifles, light as air,” compared with the bewildering question “What is a Thing?”
In the Chapter on Propositions of Relation I have inserted a new Section, containing the proof that a Proposition, beginning with “All,” is a Double Proposition (a fact that is quite independent of the arbitrary rule, laid down in the next Section, that such a Proposition is to be understood as implying the actual existence of its Subject). This proof was given, in the earlier editions, incidentally, in the course of the discussion of the Biliteral Diagram: but its proper place, in this treatise, is where I have now introduced it.
In the Sorites-Examples, I have made a good many verbal alterations, in order to evade a pg_ix difficulty, which I fear will have perplexed some of the Readers of the first three Editions. Some of the Premisses were so worded that their Terms were not Specieses of the Univ. named in the Dictionary, but of a larger Class, of which the Univ. was only a portion. In all such cases, it was intended that the Reader should perceive that what was asserted of the larger Class was thereby asserted of the Univ., and should ignore, as superfluous, all that it asserted of its other portion. Thus, in Ex. 15, the Univ. was stated to be “ducks in this village,” and the third Premiss was “Mrs. Bond has no gray ducks,” i.e. “No gray ducks are ducks belonging to Mrs. Bond.” Here the Terms are not Specieses of the Univ., but of the larger Class “ducks,” of which the Univ. is only a portion: and it was intended that the Reader should perceive that what is here asserted of “ ducks” is thereby asserted of “ ducks in this village.” and should treat this Premiss as if it were “Mrs. Bond has no gray ducks in this village,” and should ignore, as superfluous, what it asserts as to the other portion of the Class “ducks,” viz. “ Mrs. Bond has no gray ducks out of this village”.
In the Appendix I have given a new version of the Problem of the “Five Liars.” My object, in doing so, is to escape the subtle and mysterious difficulties which beset all attempts at regarding a Proposition as being its own Subject, or a Set of Propositions as being Subjects for one another. It is certainly, a most bewildering and unsatisfactory theory: one cannot help feeling that there is a great lack of substance in all this shadowy host——that, as the procession of phantoms glides before us, there is not one that we can pounce upon, and say “Here is a Proposition that must be either true or false!”——that it is but a Barmecide Feast, to which we have been bidden——and that its prototype is to be found in that mythical island, whose inhabitants “earned a precarious living by taking in each others washing”! By simply translating “telling 2 Truths” into “taking both of 2 condiments (salt and mustard),” “telling 2 Lies” into “taking neither of them” and “telling a Truth and a Lie (order not specified)” into “taking only one condiment (it is not specified which),” I have escaped all pg_x those metaphysical puzzles, and have produced a Problem which, when translated into a Set of symbolized Premisses, furnishes the very same Data as were furnished by the Problem of the “Five Liars.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
4/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
The coined words, introduced in previous editions, such as “Eliminands” and “Retinends”, perhaps hardly need any apology: they were indispensable to my system: but the new plural, here used for the first time, viz. “Soriteses”, will, I fear, be condemned as “bad English”, unless I say a word in its defence. We have three singular nouns, in English, of plural form, “series”, “species”, and “Sorites”: in all three, the awkwardness, of using the same word for both singular and plural, must often have been felt: this has been remedied, in the case of “series” by coining the plural “serieses”, which has already found it way into the dictionaries: so I am no rash innovator, but am merely “following suit”, in using the new plural “Soriteses”.
In conclusion, let me point out that even those, who are obliged to study Formal Logic, with a view to being able to answer Examination-Papers in that subject, will find the study of Symbolic Logic most helpful for this purpose, in throwing light upon many of the obscurities with which Formal Logic abounds, and in furnishing a delightfully easy method of testing the results arrived at by the cumbrous processes which Formal Logic enforces upon its votaries.
This is, I believe, the very first attempt (with the exception of my own little book, The Game of Logic, published in 1886, a very incomplete performance) that has been made to popularise this fascinating subject. It has cost me years of hard work: but if it should prove, as I hope it may, to be of real service to the young, and to be taken up, in High Schools and in private families, as a valuable addition to their stock of healthful mental recreations, such a result would more than repay ten times the labour that I have expended on it.
29, Bedford Street, Strand. Christmas, 1896.
INTRODUCTION.
L. C.
pg_xi
TO LEARNERS.
[N.B. Some remarks, addressed to Teachers, will be found in the Appendix, at p. 165.]
The Learner, who wishes to try the question fairly, whether this little book does, or does not, supply the materials for a most interesting mental recreation, is earnestly advised to adopt the following Rules:—
(1) Begin at the beginning, and do not allow yourself to gratify a mere idle curiosity by dipping into the book, here and there. This would very likely lead to your throwing it aside, with the remark “This is much too hard for me!”, and thus losing the chance of adding a very large item to your stock of mental delights. This Rule (of not dipping) is very desirable with other kinds of books——such as novels, for instance, where you may easily spoil much of the enjoyment you would otherwise get from the story, by dipping into it further on, so that what the author meant to be a pleasant surprise comes to you as a matter of course. Some people, I know, make a practice of looking into Vol. III first, just to see how the story ends: and perhaps it is as well just to know that all ends happily——that the muchpersecuted lovers do marry after all, that he is proved to be quite innocent of the murder, that the wicked cousin is completely foiled in his plot and gets the punishment he deserves, and that the rich uncle in India (Qu. Why in India? Ans. Because, somehow, uncles never can get rich anywhere else) dies at exactly the right moment——before taking the trouble to read Vol. I. This, I say, is just permissible with a novel, where Vol. III has a meaning, even for those who have not read the earlier part of the story; but, with a scientific book, it is
pg_xii
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
5/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
sheer insanity: you will find the latter part hopelessly unintelligible, if you read it before reaching it in regular course.
(2) Dont begin any fresh Chapter, or Section, until you are certain that you thoroughly understand the whole book up to that point, and that you have worked, correctly, most if not all of the examples which have been set. So long as you are conscious that all the land you have passed through is absolutely conquered, and that you are leaving no unsolved difficulties behind you, which will be sure to turn up again later on, your triumphal progress will be easy and delightful. Otherwise, you will find your state of puzzlement get worse and worse as you proceed, till you give up the whole thing in utter disgust.
(3) When you come to any passage you dont understand, read it again: if you still dont understand it, read it again: if you fail, even after three readings, very likely your brain is getting a little tired. In that case, put the book away, and take to other occupations, and next day, when you come to it fresh, you will very likely find that it is quite easy.
(4) If possible, find some genial friend, who will read the book along with you, and will talk over the difficulties with you. Talking is a wonderful smoother-over of difficulties. When I come upon anything——in Logic or in any other hard subject——that entirely puzzles me, I find it a capital plan to talk it over, aloud, even when I am all alone. One can explain things so clearly to ones self! And then, you know, one is so patient with ones self: one never gets irritated at ones own stupidity!
If, dear Reader, you will faithfully observe these Rules, and so give my little book a really fair trial, I promise you, most confidently, that you will find Symbolic Logic to be one of the most, if not the most, fascinating of mental recreations! In this First Part, I have carefully avoided all difficulties which seemed to me to be beyond the grasp of an intelligent child of (say) twelve or fourteen years of age. I have myself taught most of its contents, vivâ voce, to many children, and have found them take a real intelligent interest in the subject. For those, who succeed in mastering Part I, and who begin, like Oliver, “asking for more,” I hope to provide, in Part II, some tolerably hard nuts to crack——nuts that will require all the nut-crackers they happen to possess!
pg_xiii
Mental recreation is a thing that we all of us need for our mental health; and you may get much healthy enjoyment, no doubt, from Games, such as Back-gammon, Chess, and the new Game “Halma”. But, after all, when you have made yourself a first-rate player at any one of these Games, you have nothing real to show for it, as a result! You enjoyed the Game, and the victory, no doubt, at the time: but you have no result that you can treasure up and get real good out of. And, all the while, you have been leaving unexplored a perfect mine of wealth. Once master the machinery of Symbolic Logic, and you have a mental occupation always at hand, of absorbing interest, and one that will be of real use to you in any subject you may take up. It will give you clearness of thought——the ability to see your way through a puzzle——the habit of arranging your ideas in an orderly and get-atable form——and, more valuable than all, the power to detect fallacies, and to tear to pieces the flimsy illogical arguments, which you will so continually encounter in books, in newspapers, in speeches, and even in sermons, and which so easily delude those who have never taken the trouble to master this fascinating Art. Try it. That is all I ask of you!
29, Bedford Street, Strand. February 21, 1896.
CONTENTS
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
L. C.
pg_xiv pg_xv
6/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
BOOK I.
THINGS AND THEIR ATTRIBUTES. CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
Things Attributes Adjuncts
CHAPTER II.
CLASSIFICATION.
Classification Class Peculiar Attributes Genus Species Differentia Real and Unreal, or Imaginary, Classes Individual A Class regarded as a single Thing
Division Codivisional Classes
CHAPTER III.
DIVISION.
§ 1. Introductory.
Dichotomy Arbitrary limits of Classes Subdivision of Classes
§ 2. Dichotomy.
CHAPTER IV.
NAMES.
Name Real and Unreal Names Three ways of expressing a Name
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
page
1 〃 〃
1½ 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 2 〃 2½
pg_xvi
3 〃
3½ 〃 4
4½ 〃 〃
7/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Two senses in which a plural Name may be used
5
CHAPTER V.
DEFINITIONS.
Definition
6
Examples worked as models
BOOK II.
PROPOSITIONS.
pg_xvii
CHAPTER I.
PROPOSITIONS GENERALLY.
§ 1. Introductory.
Technical meaning of “some”
8
Proposition
Normal form of a Proposition
Subject, Predicate, and Terms
9
Its four parts:—
§ 2. Normal form of a Proposition.
(1) Sign of Quantity
(2) Name of Subject
(3) Copula
(4) Name of Predicate
§ 3. Various kinds of Propositions. Three kinds of Propositions:—
(1) Begins with “Some”. Called a Particular Proposition: also a Proposition
in I
10
(2) Begins with “No”. Called a Universal Negative Proposition: also a
Proposition in E
(3) Begins with “All”. Called a Universal Affirmative Proposition: also a
Proposition in A
A Proposition, whose Subject is an Individual, is to be regarded as Universal
Two kinds of Propositions, Propositions of Existence, and Propositions of Relation
pg_xviii
CHAPTER II.
PROPOSITIONS OF EXISTENCE.
Proposition of Existence
11
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
8/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
CHAPTER III.
PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION.
§ 1. Introductory.
Proposition of Relation
12
Universe of Discourse, or Univ.
§ 2. Reduction of a Proposition of Relation to Normal form.
Rules
13
Examples worked
§ 3.
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, is a Double Proposition.
Its equivalence to two Propositions
17
§ 4. What is implied, in a Proposition of Relation, as to the Reality of its Terms? Propositions beginning with “Some”
Propositions beginning with “No”
Propositions beginning with “All”
pg_xix
19 〃 〃
§ 5.
Translation of a Proposition of Relation into one or more Propositions of Existence.
Rules
20
Examples worked
BOOK III.
THE BILITERAL DIAGRAM.
CHAPTER I.
SYMBOLS AND CELLS.
The Diagram assigned to a certain Set of Things, viz. our Univ.
22
Univ. divided into the x-Class and the x-Class
23
The North and South Halves assigned to these two Classes
The x-Class subdivided into the xy-Class and the xy-Class
The North-West and North-East Cells assigned to these two Classes
The x-Class similarly divided
The South-West and South-East Cells similarly assigned
The West and East Halves have thus been assigned to the y-Class and the y-Class
Table I. Attributes of Classes, and Compartments, or Cells, assigned to them
25
CHAPTER II.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg_xx
9/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
COUNTERS.
Meaning of a Red Counter placed in a Cell
26
Meaning of a Red Counter placed on a Partition
American phrase “sitting on the fence”
Meaning of a Grey Counter placed in a Cell
CHAPTER III.
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS.
§ 1.
Introductory.
The word “Things” to be henceforwards omitted
27
Uniliteral Proposition
Biliteral do.
Proposition in terms of certain Letters
§ 2.
Representation of Propositions of Existence.
The Proposition “Some x exist”
28
Three other similar Propositions
The Proposition “No x exist”
Three other similar Propositions
29
The Proposition “Some xy exist”
Three other similar Propositions
The Proposition “No xy exist”
Three other similar Propositions
The Proposition “No x exist” is Double, and is equivalent to the two Propositions “No
xy exist” and “No xy exist”
30
§ 3. Representation of Propositions of Relations.
The Proposition “Some x are y”
Three other similar Propositions
The Proposition “Some y are x”
31
Three other similar Propositions
Trio of equivalent Propositions, viz. “Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are
x”
Converse Propositions, and Conversion
Three other similar Trios
32
The Proposition “No x are y”
Three other similar Propositions
The Proposition “No y are x”
Three other similar Propositions
Trio of equivalent Propositions, viz. “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”
33
Three other similar Trios
pg_xxi
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
10/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
The Proposition “All x are y” is Double, and is equivalent to the two Propositions
“Some x are y” and “No x are y
Seven other similar Propositions
34
Table II. Representation of Propositions of Existence
34
Table III. Representation of Propositions of Relation
35
CHAPTER IV.
INTERPRETATION OF BILITERAL DIAGRAM, WHEN MARKED WITH COUNTERS.
Interpretation of And of three other similar arrangements Interpretation of And of three other similar arrangements Interpretation of And of three other similar arrangements Interpretation of And of three other similar arrangements Interpretation of And of three other similar arrangements Interpretation of
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
36 〃 〃 pg_xxii 〃 37 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃
11/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
And of seven other similar arrangements
38
BOOK IV.
THE TRILITERAL DIAGRAM.
CHAPTER I.
SYMBOLS AND CELLS.
Change of Biliteral into Triliteral Diagram
39
The xy-Class subdivided into the xym-Class and the xym-Class
40
The Inner and Outer Cells of the North-West Quarter assigned to these Classes
The xy-Class, the xy-Class, and the xy-Class similarly subdivided
The Inner and Outer Cells of the North-East, the South-West, and the South-East
Quarter similarly assigned
The Inner Square and the Outer Border have thus been assigned to the m-Class and
the m-Class
Rules for finding readily the Compartment, or Cell, assigned to any given Attribute or
Attributes
Table IV. Attributes of Classes, and Compartments, or Cells, assigned to them
42
pg_xxiii
CHAPTER II.
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS IN TERMS OF x AND m, OR OF y AND m.
§ 1.
Representation of Propositions of Existence in terms of x and m, or of y and m.
The Proposition “Some xm exist”
43
Seven other similar Propositions
The Proposition “No xm exist”
44
Seven other similar Propositions
§ 2. Representation of Propositions of Relation in terms of x and m, or of y and m.
The Pair of Converse Propositions “Some x are m” = “Some m are x”
Seven other similar Pairs
The Pair of Converse Propositions “No x are m” = “No m are x”
Seven other similar Pairs
The Proposition “All x are m”
45
Fifteen other similar Propositions
Table V. Representations of Propositions in terms of x and m
46
Table VI. Representations of Propositions in terms of y and m
47
Table VII. Representations of Propositions in terms of x and m
48
Table VIII. Representations of Propositions in terms of y and m
49
CHAPTER III.
REPRESENTATION OF TWO PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION, ONE IN TERMS OF x AND m, AND
pg_xxiv
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
12/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
THE OTHER IN TERMS OF y AND m, ON THE SAME DIAGRAM.
The Digits “I” and “O” to be used instead of Red and Grey Counters
50
Rules
Examples worked
CHAPTER IV.
INTERPRETATION, IN TERMS OF x AND y, OF TRILITERAL DIAGRAM, WHEN MARKED WITH COUNTERS OR DIGITS.
Rules
53
Examples worked
54
BOOK V.
SYLLOGISMS.
Syllogism Premisses Conclusion Eliminands Retinends Consequent The Symbol “∴” Specimen-Syllogisms
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
CHAPTER II.
PROBLEMS IN SYLLOGISMS.
§ 1. Introductory. Concrete and Abstract Propositions Method of translating a Proposition from concrete into abstract form Two forms of Problems
§ 2. Given a Pair of Propositions of Relation, which contain between them a Pair of codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as Premisses: to ascertain what
Conclusion, if any, is consequent from them. Rules
Examples worked fully The same worked briefly, as models
§ 3.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
56 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 57
pg_xxv
59 〃 〃
60 〃 64
13/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Given a Trio of Propositions of Relation, of which every two contain a Pair of
codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as a Syllogism: to ascertain whether
the proposed Conclusion is consequent from the proposed Premisses, and, if so,
whether it is complete.
Rules
66
Examples worked briefly, as models
BOOK VI.
THE METHOD OF SUBSCRIPTS.
Meaning of x1, xy1, &c. Entity Meaning of x0, xy0, &c. Nullity The Symbols “†” and “¶” Like and unlike Signs
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
CHAPTER II.
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION.
The Pair of Converse Propositions “Some x are y” = “Some y are x” Three other similar Pairs The Pair of Converse Propositions “No x are y” = “No y are x” Three other similar Pairs The Proposition “All x are y” The Proposition “All x are y” is Double, and is equivalent to the two Propositions “Some x exist” and “No x and y” Seven other similar Propositions Rule for translating “All x are y” from abstract into subscript form, and vice versâ
Rules
CHAPTER III.
SYLLOGISMS.
§ 1. Representation of Syllogisms.
§ 2. Formulæ for Syllogisms. Three Formulæ worked out:— Fig. I. xm0 † ym0 ¶ xy0
its two Variants (α) and (β)
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg_xxvi
70 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃
71 〃 〃 〃 72 〃 〃 〃
pg_xxvii
73
75 〃
14/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Fig. II. xm0 † ym1 ¶ xy1 Fig. III. xm0 † ym0 † m1 ¶ xy1 Table IX. Formulæ and Rules Examples worked briefly, as models
Symbolic Logic
§ 3. Fallacies. Fallacy Method of finding Forms of Fallacies
Forms best stated in words Three Forms of Fallacies:—
(1) Fallacy of Like Eliminands not asserted to exist (2) Fallacy of Unlike Eliminands with an Entity-Premiss
(3) Fallacy of two Entity-Premisses
Rules
§ 4. Method of proceeding with a given Pair of Propositions.
BOOK VII. SORITESES.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
Sorites Premisses Partial Conclusion Complete Conclusion (or Conclusion) Eliminands Retinends consequent The Symbol “∴” Specimen-Soriteses
Form of Problem Two Methods of Solution
CHAPTER II.
PROBLEMS IN SORITESES.
§ 1. Introductory.
Rules Example worked
§ 2. Solution by Method of Separate Syllogisms.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
76 77 78 〃
81 82 〃 〃 83 〃
84
pg_xxviii
85 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 〃 86
87 〃
88 〃
15/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Underscoring
§ 3. Solution by Method of Underscoring.
Subscripts to be omitted Example worked fully Example worked briefly, as model Seventeen Examination-Papers
pg_xxix
91 〃 92 93 94
BOOK VIII.
EXAMPLES, WITH ANSWERS AND SOLUTIONS.
CHAPTER I.
EXAMPLES.
§ 1.
Propositions of Relation, to be reduced to normal form
97
§ 2.
Pairs of Abstract Propositions, one in terms of x and m, and the other in terms of y
and m, to be represented on the same Triliteral Diagram
98
§ 3.
Marked Triliteral Diagrams, to be interpreted in terms of x and y
99
§ 4. Pairs of Abstract Propositions, proposed as Premisses: Conclusions to be found 100
§ 5. Pairs of Concrete Propositions, proposed as Premisses: Conclusions to be found
pg_xxx
101
§ 6.
Trios of Abstract Propositions, proposed as Syllogisms: to be examined
106
§ 7.
Trios of Concrete Propositions, proposed as Syllogisms: to be examined
107
§ 8.
Sets of Abstract Propositions, proposed as Premisses for Soriteses: Conclusions to be
found
110
§ 9.
Sets of Concrete Propositions, proposed as Premisses for Soriteses: Conclusions to be
found
112
CHAPTER II.
ANSWERS.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
16/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Answers to § 1 § 2 § 3
§ 4 § 5 § 6 § 7 § 8
§ 9
Symbolic Logic
CHAPTER III.
SOLUTIONS.
§ 1. Propositions of Relation reduced to normal form. Solutions for § 1
Solutions for § 4 Nos. 1 to 12 § 5 〃 1 to 12 § 6 〃 1 to 10 § 7 〃 1 to 6
§ 2. Method of Diagrams.
Solutions for § 4 § 5 Nos. 13 to 24 § 6 § 7 § 8 § 9
§ 3. Method of Subscripts.
NOTES
APPENDIX, ADDRESSED TO TEACHERS
NOTES TO APPENDIX
§ 1. Tables § 2. Words &c. explained
INDEX.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
125 126 127 〃 128 130 131 132 〃
pg_xxxi
134
136 138 141 144
146 147 148 150 155 157
164
165
195
197 〃
17/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
BOOK I.
pg_xxxii pg001
THINGS AND THEIR ATTRIBUTES.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
The Universe contains Things.
[For example, “I,” “London,” “roses,” “redness,” “old English books,” “the letter which I received yesterday.”]
Things have Attributes.
[For example, “large,” “red,” “old,” “which I received yesterday.”]
One Thing may have many Attributes; and one Attribute may belong to many Things.
[Thus, the Thing “a rose” may have the Attributes “red,” “scented,” “full-blown,” &c.; and the Attribute “red” may belong to the Things “a rose,” “a brick,” “a ribbon,” &c.]
Any Attribute, or any Set of Attributes, may be called an Adjunct.
[This word is introduced in order to avoid the constant repetition of the phrase “Attribute or Set of Attributes.”
Thus, we may say that a rose has the Attribute “red” (or the Adjunct “red,” whichever we prefer); or we may say that it has the Adjunct “red, scented and fullblown.”]
CHAPTER II.
pg001½
CLASSIFICATION.
Classification, or the formation of Classes, is a Mental Process, in which we imagine that we have put together, in a group, certain Things. Such a group is called a Class.
This Process may be performed in three different ways, as follows:—
(1) We may imagine that we have put together all Things. The Class so formed (i.e. the Class “Things”) contains the whole Universe.
(2) We may think of the Class “Things,” and may imagine that we have picked out from it all the Things which possess a certain Adjunct not possessed by the whole Class. This Adjunct is said to be peculiar to the Class so formed. In this case, the Class “Things” is called a Genus with regard to the Class so formed: the Class, so formed, is called a Species of the Class “Things”: and its peculiar Adjunct is called its Differentia.
As this Process is entirely Mental, we can perform it whether there is, or is not, an existing Thing which possesses that Adjunct. If there is, the Class is said to be Real; if not, it is said to be Unreal, or Imaginary.
pg002
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
18/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[For example, we may imagine that we have picked out, from the Class “Things,” all the Things which possess the Adjunct “material, artificial, consisting of houses and streets”; and we may thus form the Real Class “towns.” Here we may regard “Things” as a Genus, “Towns” as a Species of Things, and “material, artificial, consisting of houses and streets” as its Differentia.
Again, we may imagine that we have picked out all the Things which possess the Adjunct “weighing a ton, easily lifted by a baby”; and we may thus form the Imaginary Class “Things that weigh a ton and are easily lifted by a baby.”]
(3) We may think of a certain Class, not the Class “Things,” and may imagine that we have picked out from it all the Members of it which possess a certain Adjunct not possessed by the whole Class. This Adjunct is said to be peculiar to the smaller Class so formed. In this case, the Class thought of is called a Genus with regard to the smaller Class picked out from it: the smaller Class is called a Species of the larger: and its peculiar Adjunct is called its Differentia.
[For example, we may think of the Class “towns,” and imagine that we have picked out from it all the towns which possess the Attribute “lit with gas”; and we may thus form the Real Class “towns lit with gas.” Here we may regard “Towns” as a Genus, “Towns lit with gas” as a Species of Towns, and “lit with gas” as its Differentia.
If, in the above example, we were to alter “lit with gas” into “paved with gold,” we should get the Imaginary Class “towns paved with gold.”]
A Class, containing only one Member is called an Individual.
[For example, the Class “towns having four million inhabitants,” which Class contains only one Member, viz. “London.”]
Hence, any single Thing, which we can name so as to distinguish it from all other Things, may be regarded as a one-Member Class.
pg002½
[Thus “London” may be regarded as the one-Member Class, picked out from the Class “towns,” which has, as its Differentia, “having four million inhabitants.”]
A Class, containing two or more Members, is sometimes regarded as one single Thing. When so regarded, it may possess an Adjunct which is not possessed by any Member of it taken separately.
[Thus, the Class “The soldiers of the Tenth Regiment,” when regarded as one single Thing, may possess the Attribute “formed in square,” which is not possessed by any Member of it taken separately.]
CHAPTER III.
pg003
DIVISION.
§ 1.
Introductory.
Division is a Mental Process, in which we think of a certain Class of Things, and imagine that we have divided it into two or more smaller Classes.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
19/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Thus, we might think of the Class “books,” and imagine that we had divided it into the two smaller Classes “bound books” and “unbound books,” or into the three Classes, “books priced at less than a shilling,” “shilling-books,” “books priced at more than a shilling,” or into the twenty-six Classes, “books whose names begin with A,” “books whose names begin with B,” &c.]
A Class, that has been obtained by a certain Division, is said to be codivisional with every Class obtained by that Division.
[Thus, the Class “bound books” is codivisional with each of the two Classes, “bound books” and “unbound books.”
Similarly, the Battle of Waterloo may be said to have been “contemporary” with every event that happened in 1815.]
Hence a Class, obtained by Division, is codivisional with itself.
[Thus, the Class “bound books” is codivisional with itself.
Similarly, the Battle of Waterloo may be said to have been “contemporary” with itself.]
§ 2.
pg003½
Dichotomy.
If we think of a certain Class, and imagine that we have picked out from it a certain smaller Class, it is evident that the Remainder of the large Class does not possess the Differentia of that smaller Class. Hence it may be regarded as another smaller Class, whose Differentia may be formed, from that of the Class first picked out, by prefixing the word “not”; and we may imagine that we have divided the Class first thought of into two smaller Classes, whose Differentiæ are contradictory. This kind of Division is called Dichotomy.
[For example, we may divide “books” into the two Classes whose Differentiæ are “old” and “not-old.”]
In performing this Process, we may sometimes find that the Attributes we have chosen are used so loosely, in ordinary conversation, that it is not easy to decide which of the Things belong to the one Class and which to the other. In such a case, it would be necessary to lay down some arbitrary rule, as to where the one Class should end and the other begin.
[Thus, in dividing “books” into “old” and “not-old,” we may say “Let all books printed before a.d. 1801, be regarded as old, and all others as not-old.”]
Henceforwards let it be understood that, if a Class of Things be divided into two Classes, whose Differentiæ have contrary meanings, each Differentia is to be regarded as equivalent to the other with the word “not” prefixed.
[Thus, if “books” be divided into “old” and “new” the Attribute “old” is to be regarded as equivalent to “not-new,” and the Attribute “new” as equivalent to “notold.”]
After dividing a Class, by the Process of Dichotomy, into two smaller Classes, we may sub- pg004 divide each of these into two still smaller Classes; and this Process may be repeated over and over again, the number of Classes being doubled at each repetition.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
20/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[For example, we may divide “books” into “old” and “new” (i.e. “not-old”): we may then sub-divide each of these into “English” and “foreign” (i.e. “notEnglish”), thus getting four Classes, viz.
(1) old English; (2) old foreign; (3) new English; (4) new foreign.
If we had begun by dividing into “English” and “foreign,” and had then subdivided into “old” and “new,” the four Classes would have been
(1) English old; (2) English new; (3) foreign old; (4) foreign new.
The Reader will easily see that these are the very same four Classes which we had before.]
CHAPTER IV.
pg004½
NAMES.
The word “Thing”, which conveys the idea of a Thing, without any idea of an Adjunct, represents any single Thing. Any other word (or phrase), which conveys the idea of a Thing, with the idea of an Adjunct represents any Thing which possesses that Adjunct; i.e., it represents any Member of the Class to which that Adjunct is peculiar.
Such a word (or phrase) is called a Name; and, if there be an existing Thing which it represents, it is said to be a Name of that Thing.
[For example, the words “Thing,” “Treasure,” “Town,” and the phrases “valuable Thing,” “material artificial Thing consisting of houses and streets,” “Town lit with gas,” “Town paved with gold,” “old English Book.”]
Just as a Class is said to be Real, or Unreal, according as there is, or is not, an existing Thing in it, so also a Name is said to be Real, or Unreal, according as there is, or is not, an existing Thing represented by it.
[Thus, “Town lit with gas” is a Real Name: “Town paved with gold” is an Unreal Name.]
Every Name is either a Substantive only, or else a phrase consisting of a Substantive and one or more Adjectives (or phrases used as Adjectives).
Every Name, except “Thing”, may usually be expressed in three different forms:—
(a) The Substantive “Thing”, and one or more Adjectives (or phrases used as Adjectives) conveying the ideas of the Attributes;
(b) A Substantive, conveying the idea of a Thing with the ideas of some of the Attributes, and one or more Adjectives (or phrases used as Adjectives) conveying the ideas of the other Attributes;
pg005
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
21/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
(c) A Substantive conveying the idea of a Thing with the ideas of all the Attributes.
[Thus, the phrase “material living Thing, belonging to the Animal Kingdom, having two hands and two feet” is a Name expressed in Form (a).
If we choose to roll up together the Substantive “Thing” and the Adjectives “material, living, belonging to the Animal Kingdom,” so as to make the new Substantive “Animal,” we get the phrase “Animal having two hands and two feet,” which is a Name (representing the same Thing as before) expressed in Form (b).
And, if we choose to roll up the whole phrase into one word, so as to make the new Substantive “Man,” we get a Name (still representing the very same Thing) expressed in Form (c).]
A Name, whose Substantive is in the plural number, may be used to represent either
(1) Members of a Class, regarded as separate Things; or (2) a whole Class, regarded as one single Thing.
[Thus, when I say “Some soldiers of the Tenth Regiment are tall,” or “The soldiers of the Tenth Regiment are brave,” I am using the Name “soldiers of the Tenth Regiment” in the first sense; and it is just the same as if I were to point to each of them separately, and to say “This soldier of the Tenth Regiment is tall,” “That soldier of the Tenth Regiment is tall,” and so on.
But, when I say “The soldiers of the Tenth Regiment are formed in square,” I am using the phrase in the second sense; and it is just the same as if I were to say “The Tenth Regiment is formed in square.”]
CHAPTER V.
pg006
DEFINITIONS.
It is evident that every Member of a Species is also a Member of the Genus out of which that Species has been picked, and that it possesses the Differentia of that Species. Hence it may be represented by a Name consisting of two parts, one being a Name representing any Member of the Genus, and the other being the Differentia of that Species. Such a Name is called a Definition of any Member of that Species, and to give it such a Name is to define it.
[Thus, we may define a “Treasure” as a “valuable Thing.” In this case we regard “Things” as the Genus, and “valuable” as the Differentia.]
The following Examples, of this Process, may be taken as models for working others.
[Note that, in each Definition, the Substantive, representing a Member (or Members) of the Genus, is printed in Capitals.]
1. Define “a Treasure.”
Ans. “a valuable Thing.”
2. Define “Treasures.”
Ans. “valuable Things.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
22/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
3. Define “a Town.”
Symbolic Logic
Ans. “a material artificial Thing, consisting of houses and streets.”
4. Define “Men.”
Ans. “material, living Things, belonging to the Animal Kingdom, having two hands and two feet”;
or else
“Animals having two hands and two feet.”
5. Define “London.”
Ans. “the material artificial Thing, which consists of houses and streets, and has four million inhabitants”;
or else
“the Town which has four million inhabitants.”
[Note that we here use the article “the” instead of “a”, because we happen to know that there is only one such Thing.
The Reader can set himself any number of Examples of this Process, by simply choosing the Name of any common Thing (such as “house,” “tree,” “knife”), making a Definition for it, and then testing his answer by referring to any English Dictionary.]
pg007
BOOK II.
PROPOSITIONS.
CHAPTER I.
PROPOSITIONS GENERALLY.
§ 1.
Introductory. Note that the word “some” is to be regarded, henceforward, as meaning “one or more.” The word Proposition, as used in ordinary conversation, may be applied to any word, or phrase, which conveys any information whatever.
[Thus the words “yes” and “no” are Propositions in the ordinary sense of the word; and so are the phrases “you owe me five farthings” and “I dont!” Such words as “oh!” or “never!”, and such phrases as “fetch me that book!” “which book do you mean?” do not seem, at first sight, to convey any information; but they can easily be turned into equivalent forms which do so, viz. “I am
pg008
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
23/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
surprised,” “I will never consent to it,” “I order you to fetch me that book,” “I want to know which book you mean.”]
But a Proposition, as used in this First Part of “Symbolic Logic,” has a peculiar form, which may be called its Normal form; and if any Proposition, which we wish to use in an pg009 argument, is not in normal form, we must reduce it to such a form, before we can use it.
A Proposition, when in normal form, asserts, as to certain two Classes, which are called its Subject and Predicate, either
(1) that some Members of its Subject are Members of its Predicate;
or (2)that no Members of its Subject are Members of its Predicate;
or (3)that all Members of its Subject are Members of its Predicate.
The Subject and the Predicate of a Proposition are called its Terms.
Two Propositions, which convey the same information, are said to be equivalent.
[Thus, the two Propositions, “I see John” and “John is seen by me,” are equivalent.]
§ 2.
Normal form of a Proposition.
A Proposition, in normal form, consists of four parts, viz.—
(1) The word “some,” or “no,” or “all.” (This word, which tells us how many Members of the Subject are also Members of the Predicate, is called the Sign of Quantity.)
(2) Name of Subject.
(3) The verb “are” (or “is”). (This is called the Copula.)
(4) Name of Predicate.
§ 3.
pg010
Various kinds of Propositions.
A Proposition, that begins with “Some”, is said to be Particular. It is also called a Proposition in I.
[Note, that it is called Particular, because it refers to a part only of the Subject.]
A Proposition, that begins with “No”, is said to be Universal Negative. It is also called a Proposition in E.
A Proposition, that begins with “All”, is said to be Universal Affirmative. It is also called a Proposition in A.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
24/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Note, that they are called Universal, because they refer to the whole of the Subject.]
A Proposition, whose Subject is an Individual, is to be regarded as Universal.
[Let us take, as an example, the Proposition “John is not well”. This of course implies that there is an Individual, to whom the speaker refers when he mentions “John”, and whom the listener knows to be referred to. Hence the Class “men referred to by the speaker when he mentions John” is a one-Member Class, and the Proposition is equivalent to “All the men, who are referred to by the speaker when he mentions John, are not well.”]
Propositions are of two kinds, Propositions of Existence and Propositions of Relation.
These shall be discussed separately.
CHAPTER II.
pg011
PROPOSITIONS OF EXISTENCE.
A Proposition of Existence, when in normal form, has, for its Subject, the Class “existing Things”.
Its Sign of Quantity is “Some” or “No”.
[Note that, though its Sign of Quantity tells us how many existing Things are Members of its Predicate, it does not tell us the exact number: in fact, it only deals with two numbers, which are, in ascending order, “0” and “1 or more.”]
It is called “a Proposition of Existence” because its effect is to assert the Reality (i.e. the real existence), or else the Imaginariness, of its Predicate.
[Thus, the Proposition “Some existing Things are honest men” asserts that the Class “honest men” is Real.
This is the normal form; but it may also be expressed in any one of the following forms:—
(1) “Honest men exist”; (2) “Some honest men exist”; (3) “The Class honest men exists”; (4) “There are honest men”; (5) “There are some honest men”.
Similarly, the Proposition “No existing Things are men fifty feet high” asserts that the Class “men 50 feet high” is Imaginary.
This is the normal form; but it may also be expressed in any one of the following forms:—
(1) “Men 50 feet high do not exist”; (2) “No men 50 feet high exist”; (3) “The Class men 50 feet high does not exist”; (4) “There are not any men 50 feet high”; (5) “There are no men 50 feet high.”]
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
25/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
CHAPTER III.
pg012
PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION.
§ 1.
Introductory.
A Proposition of Relation, of the kind to be here discussed, has, for its Terms, two Specieses of the same Genus, such that each of the two Names conveys the idea of some Attribute not conveyed by the other.
[Thus, the Proposition “Some merchants are misers” is of the right kind, since “merchants” and “misers” are Specieses of the same Genus “men”; and since the Name “merchants” conveys the idea of the Attribute “mercantile”, and the name “misers” the idea of the Attribute “miserly”, each of which ideas is not conveyed by the other Name.
But the Proposition “Some dogs are setters” is not of the right kind, since, although it is true that “dogs” and “setters” are Specieses of the same Genus “animals”, it is not true that the Name “dogs” conveys the idea of any Attribute not conveyed by the Name “setters”. Such Propositions will be discussed in Part II.]
The Genus, of which the two Terms are Specieses, is called the Universe of Discourse, or (more briefly) the Univ.
The Sign of Quantity is “Some” or “No” or “All”.
[Note that, though its Sign of Quantity tells us how many Members of its Subject are also Members of its Predicate, it does not tell us the exact number: in fact, it only deals with three numbers, which are, in ascending order, “0”, “1 or more”, “the total number of Members of the Subject”.]
It is called “a Proposition of Relation” because its effect is to assert that a certain relationship exists between its Terms.
§ 2.
pg013
Reduction of a Proposition of Relation to Normal form.
The Rules, for doing this, are as follows:—
(1) Ascertain what is the Subject (i.e., ascertain what Class we are talking about);
(2) If the verb, governed by the Subject, is not the verb “are” (or “is”), substitute for it a phrase beginning with “are” (or “is”);
(3) Ascertain what is the Predicate (i.e., ascertain what Class it is, which is asserted to contain some, or none, or all, of the Members of the Subject);
(4) If the Name of each Term is completely expressed (i.e. if it contains a Substantive), there is no need to determine the Univ.; but, if either Name is incompletely expressed, and contains Attributes only, it is then necessary to determine a Univ., in order to insert its Name as the Substantive.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
26/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
(5) Ascertain the Sign of Quantity;
Symbolic Logic
(6) Arrange in the following order:—
Sign of Quantity, Subject, Copula, Predicate.
[Let us work a few Examples, to illustrate these Rules.
(1)
“Some apples are not ripe.”
(1) The Subject is “apples.”
(2) The Verb is “are.”
(3) The Predicate is “not-ripe * * *.” (As no Substantive is expressed, and we have not yet settled what the Univ. is to be, we are forced to leave a blank.)
(4) Let Univ. be “fruit.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “some.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“Some | apples | are | not-ripe fruit.”
(2)
“None of my speculations have brought me as much as 5 per cent.”
(1) The Subject is “my speculations.”
(2) The Verb is “have brought,” for which we substitute the phrase “are * * * that have brought”.
(3) The Predicate is “* * * that have brought &c.”
(4) Let Univ. be “transactions.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “none of.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“None of | my speculations | are | transactions that have brought me as much as 5 per cent.”
(3)
“None but the brave deserve the fair.”
To begin with, we note that the phrase “none but the brave” is equivalent to “no not-brave.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg014
27/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
(1) The Subject has for its Attribute “not-brave.” But no Substantive is supplied. So we express the Subject as “not-brave * * *.”
(2) The Verb is “deserve,” for which we substitute the phrase “are deserving of”.
(3) The Predicate is “* * * deserving of the fair.”
(4) Let Univ. be “persons.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “no.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“No | not-brave persons | are | persons deserving of the fair.”
(4)
“A lame puppy would not say “thank you” if you offered to lend it a skippingrope.”
(1) The Subject is evidently “lame puppies,” and all the rest of the sentence must somehow be packed into the Predicate.
(2) The Verb is “would not say,” &c., for which we may substitute the phrase “are not grateful for.”
(3) The Predicate may be expressed as “* * * not grateful for the loan of a skipping-rope.”
(4) Let Univ. be “puppies.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “all.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“All | lame puppies | are | puppies not grateful for the loan of a skippingrope.”
(5)
“No one takes in the Times, unless he is well-educated.”
(1) The Subject is evidently persons who are not well-educated (“no one” evidently means “no person”).
(2) The Verb is “takes in,” for which we may substitute the phrase “are persons taking in.”
(3) The Predicate is “persons taking in the Times.”
(4) Let Univ. be “persons.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “no.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg015
28/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
“No | persons who are not well-educated | are | persons taking in the Times.”
(6)
“My carriage will meet you at the station.”
(1) The Subject is “my carriage.” This, being an Individual, is equivalent to the Class “my carriages.” (Note that this Class contains only one Member.)
(2) The Verb is “will meet”, for which we may substitute the phrase “are * * * that will meet.”
(3) The Predicate is “* * * that will meet you at the station.”
(4) Let Univ. be “things.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “all.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“All | my carriages | are | things that will meet you at the station.”
(7)
“Happy is the man who does not know what toothache means!”
(1) The Subject is evidently “the man &c.” (Note that in this sentence, the Predicate comes first.) At first sight, the Subject seems to be an Individual; but on further consideration, we see that the article “the” does not imply that there is only one such man. Hence the phrase “the man who” is equivalent to “all men who”.
(2) The Verb is “are.”
(3) The Predicate is “happy * * *.”
(4) Let Univ. be “men.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “all.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“All | men who do not know what toothache means | are | happy men.”
(8)
“Some farmers always grumble at the weather, whatever it may be.”
(1) The Subject is “farmers.”
(2) The Verb is “grumble,” for which we substitute the phrase “are * * * who grumble.”
(3) The Predicate is “* * * who always grumble &c.”
(4) Let Univ. be “persons.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg016
29/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “some.”
Symbolic Logic
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“Some | farmers | are | persons who always grumble at the weather, whatever it may be.”
(9)
“No lambs are accustomed to smoke cigars.”
(1) The Subject is “lambs.”
(2) The Verb is “are.”
(3) The Predicate is “* * * accustomed &c.”
(4) Let Univ. be “animals.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “no.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“No | lambs | are | animals accustomed to smoke cigars.”
(10)
“I cant understand examples that are not arranged in regular order, like those I am used to.”
(1) The Subject is “examples that,” &c.
(2) The Verb is “I cant understand,” which we must alter, so as to have “examples,” instead of “I,” as the nominative case. It may be expressed as “are not understood by me.”
(3) The Predicate is “* * * not understood by me.”
(4) Let Univ. be “examples.”
(5) The Sign of Quantity is “all.”
(6) The Proposition now becomes
“All | examples that are not arranged in regular order like those I am used to | are | examples not understood by me.”]
§ 3.
pg017
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, is a Double Proposition.
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, asserts (as we already know) that “All Members of the Subject are Members of the Predicate”. This evidently contains, as a part of what it tells us, the smaller Proposition “Some Members of the Subject are Members of the Predicate”.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
30/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Thus, the Proposition “All bankers are rich men” evidently contains the smaller Proposition “Some bankers are rich men”.]
The question now arises “What is the rest of the information which this Proposition gives us?”
In order to answer this question, let us begin with the smaller Proposition, “Some Members of the Subject are Members of the Predicate,” and suppose that this is all we have been told; and let us proceed to inquire what else we need to be told, in order to know that “All Members of the Subject are Members of the Predicate”.
[Thus, we may suppose that the Proposition “Some bankers are rich men” is all the information we possess; and we may proceed to inquire what other Proposition needs to be added to it, in order to make up the entire Proposition “All bankers are rich men”.]
Let us also suppose that the Univ. (i.e. the Genus, of which both the Subject and the Predicate are Specieses) has been divided (by the Process of Dichotomy) into two smaller Classes, viz.
(1) the Predicate;
(2) the Class whose Differentia is contradictory to that of the Predicate.
[Thus, we may suppose that the Genus “men,” (of which both “bankers” and “rich men” are Specieses) has been divided into the two smaller Classes, “rich men”, “poor men”.]
Now we know that every Member of the Subject is (as shown at p. 6) a Member of the Univ. Hence every Member of the Subject is either in Class (1) or else in Class (2).
pg018
[Thus, we know that every banker is a Member of the Genus “men”. Hence, every banker is either in the Class “rich men”, or else in the Class “poor men”.]
Also we have been told that, in the case we are discussing, some Members of the Subject are in Class (1). What else do we need to be told, in order to know that all of them are there? Evidently we need to be told that none of them are in Class (2); i.e. that none of them are Members of the Class whose Differentia is contradictory to that of the Predicate.
[Thus, we may suppose we have been told that some bankers are in the Class “rich men”. What else do we need to be told, in order to know that all of them are there? Evidently we need to be told that none of them are in the Class “poor men”.]
Hence a Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, is a Double Proposition, and is equivalent to (i.e. gives the same information as) the two Propositions
(1) “Some Members of the Subject are Members of the Predicate”;
(2) “No Members of the Subject are Members of the Class whose Differentia is contradictory to that of the Predicate”.
[Thus, the Proposition “All bankers are rich men” is a Double Proposition, and is equivalent to the two Propositions
(1) “Some bankers are rich men”;
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
31/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
(2) “No bankers are poor men”.]
Symbolic Logic
§ 4.
pg019
What is implied, in a Proposition of Relation, as to the Reality of its Terms?
Note that the rules, here laid down, are arbitrary, and only apply to Part I of my “Symbolic Logic.”
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “Some”, is henceforward to be understood as asserting that there are some existing Things, which, being Members of the Subject, are also Members of the Predicate; i.e. that some existing Things are Members of both Terms at once. Hence it is to be understood as implying that each Term, taken by itself, is Real.
[Thus, the Proposition “Some rich men are invalids” is to be understood as asserting that some existing Things are “rich invalids”. Hence it implies that each of the two Classes, “rich men” and “invalids”, taken by itself, is Real.]
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “No”, is henceforward to be understood as asserting that there are no existing Things which, being Members of the Subject, are also Members of the Predicate; i.e. that no existing Things are Members of both Terms at once. But this implies nothing as to the Reality of either Term taken by itself.
[Thus, the Proposition “No mermaids are milliners” is to be understood as asserting that no existing Things are “mermaid-milliners”. But this implies nothing as to the Reality, or the Unreality, of either of the two Classes, “mermaids” and “milliners”, taken by itself. In this case as it happens, the Subject is Imaginary, and the Predicate Real.]
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, contains (see § 3) a similar Proposition beginning with “Some”. Hence it is to be understood as implying that each Term, taken by itself, is Real.
[Thus, the Proposition “All hyænas are savage animals” contains the Proposition “Some hyænas are savage animals”. Hence it implies that each of the two Classes, “hyænas” and “savage animals”, taken by itself, is Real.]
§ 5.
pg020
Translation of a Proposition of Relation into one or more Propositions of Existence.
We have seen that a Proposition of Relation, beginning with “Some,” asserts that some existing Things, being Members of its Subject, are also Members of its Predicate. Hence, it asserts that some existing Things are Members of both; i.e. it asserts that some existing Things are Members of the Class of Things which have all the Attributes of the Subject and the Predicate.
Hence, to translate it into a Proposition of Existence, we take “existing Things” as the new Subject, and Things, which have all the Attributes of the Subject and the Predicate, as the new Predicate.
Similarly for a Proposition of Relation beginning with “No”.
A Proposition of Relation, beginning with “All”, is (as shown in § 3) equivalent to two Propositions, one beginning with “Some” and the other with “No”, each of which we now
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
32/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
know how to translate.
Symbolic Logic
[Let us work a few Examples, to illustrate these Rules.
(1) “Some apples are not ripe.”
Here we arrange thus:—
“Some” “existing Things” “are” “not-ripe apples”
Sign of Quantity. Subject. Copula. Predicate.
or thus:—
“Some | existing Things | are | not-ripe apples.”
(2) “Some farmers always grumble at the weather, whatever it may be.”
Here we arrange thus:—
“Some | existing Things | are | farmers who always grumble at the weather, whatever it may be.”
(3) “No lambs are accustomed to smoke cigars.”
Here we arrange thus:— “No | existing Things |are | lambs accustomed to smoke cigars.” (4) “None of my speculations have brought me as much as 5 per cent.”
Here we arrange thus:—
“No | existing Things | are | speculations of mine, which have brought me as much as 5 per cent.”
(5) “None but the brave deserve the fair.”
Here we note, to begin with, that the phrase “none but the brave” is equivalent to “no not-brave men.” We then arrange thus:—
“No | existing Things | are | not-brave men deserving of the fair.”
(6) “All bankers are rich men.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg021
33/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
This is equivalent to the two Propositions “Some bankers are rich men” and “No bankers are poor men.”
Here we arrange thus:—
“Some | existing Things | are | rich bankers”; and “No | existing Things | are | poor bankers.”]
[Work Examples § 1, 14 (p. 97).]
BOOK III.
THE BILITERAL DIAGRAM.
pg022
CHAPTER I.
SYMBOLS AND CELLS.
First, let us suppose that the above Diagram is an enclosure assigned to a certain Class of Things, which we have selected as our Universe of Discourse. or, more briefly, as our Univ.
[For example, we might say “Let Univ. be books”; and we might imagine the Diagram to be a large table, assigned to all “books.”]
[The Reader is strongly advised, in reading this Chapter, not to refer to the above Diagram, but to draw a large one for himself, without any letters, and to have it by him while he reads, and keep his finger on that particular part of it, about which he is reading.]
Secondly, let us suppose that we have selected a certain Adjunct, which we may call “x,” and have divided the large Class, to which we have assigned the whole Diagram, into the two smaller Classes whose Differentiæ are “x” and “not-x” (which we may call “x”), and that we have assigned the North Half of the Diagram to the one (which we may call “the Class of x-Things,” or “the x-Class”), and the South Half to the other (which we may call “the Class of x-Things,” or “the x-Class”).
[For example, we might say “Let x mean old, so that x will mean new,” and we might suppose that we had divided books into the two Classes whose Differentiæ are “old” and “new,” and had assigned the North Half of the table to “old books” and the South Half to “new books.”]
Thirdly, let us suppose that we have selected another Adjunct, which we may call “y”, and have subdivided the x-Class into the two Classes whose Differentiæ are “y” and “y”, and that we have assigned the North-West Cell to the one (which we may call “the xy-Class”), and the North-East Cell to the other (which we may call “the xy-Class”).
pg023
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
34/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[For example, we might say “Let y mean English, so that y will mean foreign”, and we might suppose that we had subdivided “old books” into the two Classes whose Differentiæ are “English” and “foreign”, and had assigned the North-West Cell to “old English books”, and the North-East Cell to “old foreign books.”]
Fourthly, let us suppose that we have subdivided the x-Class in the same manner, and have assigned the South-West Cell to the xy-Class, and the South-East Cell to the xy-Class.
[For example, we might suppose that we had subdivided “new books” into the two Classes “new English books” and “new foreign books”, and had assigned the South-West Cell to the one, and the South-East Cell to the other.]
It is evident that, if we had begun by dividing for y and y, and had then subdivided for x and x, we should have got the same four Classes. Hence we see that we have assigned the West pg024 Half to the y-Class, and the East Half to the y-Class.
[Thus, in the above Example, we should find that we had assigned the West Half of the table to “English books” and the East Half to “foreign books.”
We have, in fact, assigned the four Quarters of the table to four different Classes of books, as here shown.]
The Reader should carefully remember that, in such a phrase as “the x-Things,” the word “Things” means that particular kind of Things, to which the whole Diagram has been assigned.
[Thus, if we say “Let Univ. be books,” we mean that we have assigned the whole Diagram to “books.” In that case, if we took “x” to mean “old”, the phrase “the xThings” would mean “the old books.”]
The Reader should not go on to the next Chapter until he is quite familiar with the blank Diagram I have advised him to draw.
He ought to be able to name, instantly, the Adjunct assigned to any Compartment named in the right-hand column of the following Table.
Also he ought to be able to name, instantly, the Compartment assigned to any Adjunct named in the left-hand column.
To make sure of this, he had better put the book into the hands of some genial friend, while he himself has nothing but the blank Diagram, and get that genial friend to question him on this Table, dodging about as much as possible. The Questions and Answers should be something like this:—
TABLE I.
Adjuncts Compartments,
of
or Cells,
Classes. assigned to them.
x
North Half.
x
South 〃
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg025
35/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
y
West 〃
y
East 〃
xy
North - West Cell.
xy
〃 East 〃
xy
South - West 〃
xy
〃 East 〃
Q. “Adjunct for West Half?” A. “y.” Q. “Compartment for xy?” A. “North-East Cell.” Q. “Adjunct for South-West Cell?” A. “xy.”
&c., &c.
After a little practice, he will find himself able to do without the blank Diagram, and will be able to see it mentally (“in my minds eye, Horatio!”) while answering the questions of his genial friend. When this result has been reached, he may safely go on to the next Chapter.
CHAPTER II.
pg026
COUNTERS.
Let us agree that a Red Counter, placed within a Cell, shall mean “This Cell is occupied” (i.e. “There is at least one Thing in it”).
Let us also agree that a Red Counter, placed on the partition between two Cells, shall mean “The Compartment, made up of these two Cells, is occupied; but it is not known whereabouts, in it, its occupants are.” Hence it may be understood to mean “At least one of these two Cells is occupied: possibly both are.”
Our ingenious American cousins have invented a phrase to describe the condition of a man who has not yet made up his mind which of two political parties he will join: such a man is said to be “sitting on the fence.” This phrase exactly describes the condition of the Red Counter.
Let us also agree that a Grey Counter, placed within a Cell, shall mean “This Cell is empty” (i.e. “There is nothing in it”).
[The Reader had better provide himself with 4 Red Counters and 5 Grey ones.]
CHAPTER III.
pg027
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS.
§ 1.
Introductory.
Henceforwards, in stating such Propositions as “Some x-Things exist” or “No x-Things are y-Things”, I shall omit the word “Things”, which the Reader can supply for himself, and shall write them as “Some x exist” or “No x are y”.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
36/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Note that the word “Things” is here used with a special meaning, as explained at p. 23.]
A Proposition, containing only one of the Letters used as Symbols for Attributes, is said to be Uniliteral.
[For example, “Some x exist”, “No y exist”, &c.]
A Proposition, containing two Letters, is said to be Biliteral.
[For example, “Some xy exist”, “No x are y”, &c.]
A Proposition is said to be in terms of the Letters it contains, whether with or without accents.
[Thus, “Some xy exist”, “No x are y”, &c., are said to be in terms of x and y.]
§ 2.
pg028
Representation of Propositions of Existence.
Let us take, first, the Proposition “Some x exist”.
[Note that this Proposition is (as explained at p. 12) equivalent to “Some existing Things are x-Things.”]
This tells us that there is at least one Thing in the North Half; that is, that the North Half is occupied. And this we can evidently represent by placing a Red Counter (here represented by a dotted circle) on the partition which divides the North Half.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “Some old books exist”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “Some x exist”, “Some y exist”, and “Some y exist”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these Propositions would be “Some new books exist”, &c.]
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No x exist”.
This tells us that there is nothing in the North Half; that is, that the North Half is empty; that is, that the North-West Cell and the NorthEast Cell are both of them empty. And this we can represent by placing two Grey Counters in the North Half, one in each Cell.
[The Reader may perhaps think that it would be enough to place a Grey Counter on the partition in the North Half, and that, just as a Red Counter, so placed, would mean “This Half is occupied”, so a Grey one would mean “This Half is empty”.
This, however, would be a mistake. We have seen that a Red Counter, so placed, would mean “At least one of these two Cells is occupied: possibly both are.” Hence a Grey one would merely mean “At least one of these two Cells is empty: possibly both are”. But what we have to represent is, that both Cells are certainly empty: and this can only be done by placing a Grey Counter in each of them.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
37/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “No old books exist”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “No x exist”, “No y exist”, and “No y exist”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “No new books exist”, &c.]
Let us take, next, the Proposition “Some xy exist”.
This tells us that there is at least one Thing in the North-West Cell; that is, that the North-West Cell is occupied. And this we can represent by placing a Red Counter in it.
pg029
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “Some old English books exist”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “Some xy exist”, “Some xy exist”, and “Some xy exist”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “Some old foreign books exist”, &c.]
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No xy exist”.
This tells us that there is nothing in the North-West Cell; that is, that the North-West Cell is empty. And this we can represent by placing a Grey Counter in it.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “No old English books exist”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “No xy exist”, “No xy exist”, and “No xy exist”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “No old foreign books exist”, &c.]
We have seen that the Proposition “No x exist” may be represented by placing two Grey Counters in the North Half, one in each Cell.
pg030
We have also seen that these two Grey Counters, taken separately, represent the two Propositions “No xy exist” and “No xy exist”. Hence we see that the Proposition “No x exist” is a Double Proposition, and is equivalent to the two Propositions “No xy exist” and “No xy exist”.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “No old books exist”. Hence this is a Double Proposition, and is equivalent to the two Propositions “No old English books exist” and “No old foreign books exist”.]
§ 3.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
38/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Representation of Propositions of Relation.
Let us take, first, the Proposition “Some x are y”.
This tells us that at least one Thing, in the North Half, is also in the West Half. Hence it must be in the space common to them, that is, in the North-West Cell. Hence the North-West Cell is occupied. And this we can represent by placing a Red Counter in it.
[Note that the Subject of the Proposition settles which Half we are to use; and that the Predicate settles in which portion of it we are to place the Red Counter.
In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “Some old books are English”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “Some x are y”, “Some x are y”, and “Some x are y”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “Some old books are foreign”, &c.]
Let us take, next, the Proposition “Some y are x”.
pg031
This tells us that at least one Thing, in the West Half, is also in the North Half. Hence it must be in the space common to them, that is, in the North-West Cell. Hence the North-West Cell is occupied. And this we can represent by placing a Red Counter in it.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “Some English books are old”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “Some y are x”, “Some y are x”, and “Some y are x”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “Some English books are new”, &c.]
We see that this one Diagram has now served to represent no less than three Propositions, viz.
(1) “Some xy exist; (2) Some x are y; (3) Some y are x”.
Hence these three Propositions are equivalent.
[In the “books” example, these Propositions would be
(1) “Some old English books exist; (2) Some old books are English; (3) Some English books are old”.]
The two equivalent Propositions, “Some x are y” and “Some y are x”, are said to be Converse to each other; and the Process, of changing one into the other, is called Converting, or Conversion.
[For example, if we were told to convert the Proposition
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
39/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“Some apples are not ripe,”
Symbolic Logic
we should first choose our Univ. (say “fruit”), and then complete the Proposition, by supplying the Substantive “fruit” in the Predicate, so that it would be
“Some apples are not-ripe fruit”;
and we should then convert it by interchanging its Terms, so that it would be
“Some not-ripe fruit are apples”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Trios of equivalent Propositions; the whole Set pg032 of four Trios being as follows:—
(1) “Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”. (2) “Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”. (3) “Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”. (4) “Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No x are y”.
This tell us that no Thing, in the North Half, is also in the West Half. Hence there is nothing in the space common to them, that is, in the North-West Cell. Hence the North-West Cell is empty. And this we can represent by placing a Grey Counter in it.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “No old books are English”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “No x are y”, and “No x are y”, and “No x are y”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “No old books are foreign”, &c.]
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No y are x”.
This tells us that no Thing, in the West Half, is also in the North Half. Hence there is nothing in the space common to them, that is, in the North-West Cell. That is, the North-West Cell is empty. And this we can represent by placing a Grey Counter in it.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would be “No English books are old”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions “No y are x”, “No y are x”, and “No y are x”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself. In the “books” example, these three Propositions would be “No English books are new”, &c.]
We see that this one Diagram has now served to present no less than three Propositions, viz.
pg033
(1) “No xy exist; (2) No x are y; (3) No y are x.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
40/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Hence these three Propositions are equivalent.
[In the “books” example, these Propositions would be
(1) “No old English books exist; (2) No old books are English; (3) No English books are old”.]
The two equivalent Propositions, “No x are y” and “No y are x”, are said to be Converse to each other.
[For example, if we were told to convert the Proposition
“No porcupines are talkative”,
we should first choose our Univ. (say “animals”), and then complete the Proposition, by supplying the Substantive “animals” in the Predicate, so that it would be
“No porcupines are talkative animals”, and we should then convert it, by interchanging its Terms, so that it would be
“No talkative animals are porcupines”.]
Similarly we may represent the three similar Trios of equivalent Propositions; the whole Set of four Trios being as follows:—
(1) “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”. (2) “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”. (3) “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”. (4) “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “All x are y”.
We know (see p. 17) that this is a Double Proposition, and equivalent to the two Propositions “Some x are y” and “No x are y”, each of which we already know how to represent.
[Note that the Subject of the given Proposition settles which Half we are to use; and that its Predicate settles in which portion of that Half we are to place the Red Counter.]
TABLE II.
pg034
Some x exist
No x exist
Some x exist
No x exist
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
41/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Some y exist
Symbolic Logic
No y exist
Some y exist
No y exist
Similarly we may represent the seven similar Propositions “All x are y”, “All x are y”, “All x are y”, “All y are x”, “All y are x”, “All y are x”, and “All y are x”.
Let us take, lastly, the Double Proposition “Some x are y and some are y”, each part of which we already know how to represent.
Similarly we may represent the three similar Propositions, “Some x are y and some are y”, “Some y are x and some are x”, “Some y are x and some are x”.
The Reader should now get his genial friend to question him, severely, on these two Tables. The Inquisitor should have the Tables before him: but the Victim should have nothing but a blank Diagram, and the Counters with which he is to represent the various Propositions named by his friend, e.g. “Some y exist”, “No y are x”, “All x are y”, &c. &c.
TABLE III.
pg035
Some xy exist = Some x are y = Some y are x
All x are y
Some xy exist = Some x are y = Some y are x
All x are y
Some xy exist = Some x are y = Some y are x
All x are y
Some xy exist = Some x are y = Some y are x
All x are y
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
42/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
No xy exist = No x are y = No y are x
No xy exist = No x are y = No y are x
No xy exist = No x are y = No y are x
No xy exist = No x are y = No y are x
Some x are y, and some are y
Symbolic Logic
All y are x
All y are x
All y are x
All y are x Some y are x and some are x
Some x are y, and some are y
Some y are x and some are x
CHAPTER IV.
pg036
INTERPRETATION OF BILITERAL DIAGRAM WHEN MARKED WITH COUNTERS.
The Diagram is supposed to be set before us, with certain Counters placed upon it; and the problem is to find out what Proposition, or Propositions, the Counters represent.
As the process is simply the reverse of that discussed in the previous Chapter, we can avail ourselves of the results there obtained, as far as they go.
First, let us suppose that we find a Red Counter placed in the NorthWest Cell.
We know that this represents each of the Trio of equivalent Propositions
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
43/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
“Some xy exist” = “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”.
Similarly we may interpret a Red Counter, when placed in the North-East, or South-West, or South-East Cell.
Next, let us suppose that we find a Grey Counter placed in the NorthWest Cell.
We know that this represents each of the Trio of equivalent Propositions
“No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”.
Similarly we may interpret a Grey Counter, when placed in the North-East, or South-West, or South-East Cell.
Next, let us suppose that we find a Red Counter placed on the partition which divides the North Half.
pg037
We know that this represents the Proposition “Some x exist.”
Similarly we may interpret a Red Counter, when placed on the partition which divides the South, or West, or East Half.
Next, let us suppose that we find two Red Counters placed in the North Half, one in each Cell.
We know that this represents the Double Proposition “Some x are y and some are y”.
Similarly we may interpret two Red Counters, when placed in the South, or West, or East Half.
Next, let us suppose that we find two Grey Counters placed in the North Half, one in each Cell.
We know that this represents the Proposition “No x exist”.
Similarly we may interpret two Grey Counters, when placed in the South, or West, or East Half.
Lastly, let us suppose that we find a Red and a Grey Counter placed in the North Half, the Red in the North-West Cell, and the Grey in the North-East Cell.
We know that this represents the Proposition, “All x are y”.
[Note that the Half, occupied by the two Counters, settles what is to be the Subject of the Proposition, and that the Cell, occupied by the Red Counter, settles what is to be its Predicate.]
Similarly we may interpret a Red and a Grey counter, when placed in any one of the seven similar positions
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg038
44/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Red in North-East, Grey in North-West; Red in South-West, Grey in South-East; Red in South-East, Grey in South-West; Red in North-West, Grey in South-West; Red in South-West, Grey in North-West; Red in North-East, Grey in South-East; Red in South-East, Grey in North-East.
Symbolic Logic
Once more the genial friend must be appealed to, and requested to examine the Reader on Tables II and III, and to make him not only represent Propositions, but also interpret Diagrams when marked with Counters.
The Questions and Answers should be like this:—
Q. Represent “No x are y.” A. Grey Counter in S.E. Cell. Q. Interpret Red Counter on E. partition. A. “Some y exist.” Q. Represent “All y are x.” A. Red in N.E. Cell; Grey in S.E. Q. Interpret Grey Counter in S.W. Cell. A. “No xy exist” = “No x are y” = “No y are x”.
&c., &c.
At first the Examinee will need to have the Board and Counters before him; but he will soon learn to dispense with these, and to answer with his eyes shut or gazing into vacancy.
[Work Examples § 1, 58 (p. 97).]
BOOK IV.
THE TRILITERAL DIAGRAM.
pg039
CHAPTER I.
SYMBOLS AND CELLS.
First, let us suppose that the above left-hand Diagram is the Biliteral Diagram that we have been using in Book III., and that we change it into a Triliteral Diagram by drawing an Inner Square, so as to divide each of its 4 Cells into 2 portions, thus making 8 Cells altogether. The right-hand Diagram shows the result.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
45/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[The Reader is strongly advised, in reading this Chapter, not to refer to the above Diagrams, but to make a large copy of the right-hand one for himself, without any letters, and to have it by him while he reads, and keep his finger on that particular part of it, about which he is reading.]
Secondly, let us suppose that we have selected a certain Adjunct, which we may call “m”, and have subdivided the xy-Class into the two Classes whose Differentiæ are m and m, and that we have assigned the N.W. Inner Cell to the one (which we may call “the Class of xymThings”, or “the xym-Class”), and the N.W. Outer Cell to the other (which we may call “the Class of xym-Things”, or “the xym-Class”).
pg040
[Thus, in the “books” example, we might say “Let m mean bound, so that m will mean unbound”, and we might suppose that we had subdivided the Class “old English books” into the two Classes, “old English bound books” and “old English unbound books”, and had assigned the N.W. Inner Cell to the one, and the N.W. Outer Cell to the other.]
Thirdly, let us suppose that we have subdivided the xy-Class, the xy-Class, and the xyClass in the same manner, and have, in each case, assigned the Inner Cell to the Class possessing the Attribute m, and the Outer Cell to the Class possessing the Attribute m.
[Thus, in the “books” example, we might suppose that we had subdivided the “new English books” into the two Classes, “new English bound books” and “new English unbound books”, and had assigned the S.W. Inner Cell to the one, and the S.W. Outer Cell to the other.]
It is evident that we have now assigned the Inner Square to the m-Class, and the Outer Border to the m-Class.
[Thus, in the “books” example, we have assigned the Inner Square to “bound books” and the Outer Border to “unbound books”.]
When the Reader has made himself familiar with this Diagram, he ought to be able to find, in a moment, the Compartment assigned to a particular pair of Attributes, or the Cell assigned to a particular trio of Attributes. The following Rules will help him in doing this: —
(1) Arrange the Attributes in the order x, y, m. (2) Take the first of them and find the Compartment assigned to it. (3) Then take the second, and find what portion of that compartment is assigned to it. (4) Treat the third, if there is one, in the same way.
pg041
[For example, suppose we have to find the Compartment assigned to ym. We say to ourselves “y has the West Half; and m has the Inner portion of that West Half.”
Again, suppose we have to find the Cell assigned to xym. We say to ourselves “x has the South Half; y has the West portion of that South Half, i.e. has the SouthWest Quarter; and m has the Outer portion of that South-West Quarter.”]
The Reader should now get his genial friend to question him on the Table given on the next page, in the style of the following specimen-Dialogue.
Q. Adjunct for South Half, Inner Portion? A. xm. Q. Compartment for m?
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
46/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
A. The Outer Border. Q. Adjunct for North-East Quarter, Outer Portion? A. xym. Q. Compartment for ym? A. West Half, Inner Portion. Q. Adjunct for South Half? A. x. Q. Compartment for xym? A. South-East Quarter, Inner Portion.
&c. &c.
TABLE IV.
Adjunct
Compartments,
of
or Cells,
Classes.
assigned to them.
x
North Half.
x
South 〃
y
West 〃
y
East 〃
m
Inner Square.
m
Outer Border.
xy
North- West Quarter.
xy
〃 East 〃
xy
South- West 〃
xy
〃 East 〃
xm
North Half, Inner Portion.
xm
〃 〃 Outer 〃
xm
South 〃 Inner
xm
〃 〃 Outer 〃
ym
West 〃 Inner
ym
〃 〃 Outer 〃
ym
East 〃 Inner
ym
〃 〃 Outer 〃
xym North- West Quarter, Inner Portion.
xym
〃 〃 〃 Outer 〃
xym
〃 East 〃 Inner
xym
〃 〃 〃 Outer 〃
xym South- West 〃 Inner
xym
〃 〃 〃 Outer 〃
xym
〃 East 〃 Inner
xym
〃 〃 〃 Outer
pg042
CHAPTER II.
pg043
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS IN TERMS OF x AND m, OR OF y AND m.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
§ 1.
47/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Representation of Propositions of Existence in terms of x and m, or of y and m.
Let us take, first, the Proposition “Some xm exist”.
[Note that the full meaning of this Proposition is (as explained at p. 12) “Some existing Things are xm-Things”.]
This tells us that there is at least one Thing in the Inner portion of the North Half; that is, that this Compartment is occupied. And this we can evidently represent by placing a Red Counter on the partition which divides it.
[In the “books” example, this Proposition would mean “Some old bound books exist” (or “There are some old bound books”).]
Similarly we may represent the seven similar Propositions, “Some xm exist”, “Some xm exist”, “Some xm exist”, “Some ym exist”, “Some ym exist”, “Some ym exist”, and “Some ym exist”.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No xm exist”.
This tells us that there is nothing in the Inner portion of the North Half; that is, that this Compartment is empty. And this we can represent by placing two Grey Counters in it, one in each Cell.
pg044
Similarly we may represent the seven similar Propositions, in terms of x and m, or of y and m, viz. “No xm exist”, “No xm exist”, &c.
These sixteen Propositions of Existence are the only ones that we shall have to represent on this Diagram.
§ 2.
Representation of Propositions of Relation in terms of x and m, or of y and m. Let us take, first, the Pair of Converse Propositions
“Some x are m” = “Some m are x.” We know that each of these is equivalent to the Proposition of Existence “Some xm exist”, which we already know how to represent.
Similarly for the seven similar Pairs, in terms of x and m, or of y and m. Let us take, next, the Pair of Converse Propositions
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
48/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“No x are m” = “No m are x.”
Symbolic Logic
We know that each of these is equivalent to the Proposition of Existence “No xm exist”, which we already know how to represent.
Similarly for the seven similar Pairs, in terms of x and m, or of y and m.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “All x are m.”
We know (see p. 18) that this is a Double Proposition, and equivalent to the two Propositions “Some x are m” and “No x are m ”, each of which we already know how to represent.
pg045
Similarly for the fifteen similar Propositions, in terms of x and m, or of y and m.
These thirty-two Propositions of Relation are the only ones that we shall have to represent on this Diagram.
The Reader should now get his genial friend to question him on the following four Tables.
The Victim should have nothing before him but a blank Triliteral Diagram, a Red Counter, and 2 Grey ones, with which he is to represent the various Propositions named by the Inquisitor, e.g. “No y are m”, “Some xm exist”, &c., &c.
TABLE V.
pg046
Some xm exist = Some x are m = Some m are x
No xm exist = No x are m = No m are x
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
49/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Some xm exist = Some x are m = Some m are x
No xm exist = No x are m = No m are x
Some xm exist = Some x are m = Some m are x
No xm exist = No x are m = No m are x
Some xm exist = Some x are m = Some m are x
No xm exist = No x are m = No m are x
TABLE VI.
Some ym exist = Some y are m = Some m are y
No ym exist = No y are m = No m are y
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg047
50/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Some ym exist = Some y are m = Some m are y
No ym exist = No y are m = No m are y
Some ym exist = Some y are m = Some m are y
No ym exist = No y are m = No m are y
Some ym exist = Some y are m = Some m are y
No ym exist = No y are m = No m are y
TABLE VII.
All x are m
All x are m
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg048
51/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
All x are m All x are m All m are x All m are x All m are x All m are x TABLE VIII. All y are m All y are m
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg049
52/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
All y are m
All y are m
All m are y
All m are y
All m are y
All m are y
CHAPTER III.
pg050
REPRESENTATION OF TWO PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION, ONE IN TERMS OF x AND m, AND THE OTHER IN TERMS OF y AND m, ON THE SAME DIAGRAM.
The Reader had better now begin to draw little Diagrams for himself, and to mark them with the Digits “I” and “O”, instead of using the Board and Counters: he may put a “I” to represent a Red Counter (this may be interpreted to mean “There is at least one Thing here”), and a “O” to represent a Grey Counter (this may be interpreted to mean “There is nothing here”).
The Pair of Propositions, that we shall have to represent, will always be, one in terms of x and m, and the other in terms of y and m.
When we have to represent a Proposition beginning with “All”, we break it up into the two Propositions to which it is equivalent.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
53/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
When we have to represent, on the same Diagram, Propositions, of which some begin with “Some” and others with “No”, we represent the negative ones first. This will sometimes save us from having to put a “I” “on a fence” and afterwards having to shift it into a Cell.
[Let us work a few examples.
(1)
“No x are m; No y are m”.
Let us first represent “No x are m”. This gives us Diagram a.
Then, representing “No y are m” on the same Diagram, we get Diagram b.
a
b
pg051
(2) “Some m are x; No m are y”.
If, neglecting the Rule, we were begin with “Some m are x”, we should get Diagram a.
And if we were then to take “No m are y”, which tells us that the Inner N.W. Cell is empty, we should be obliged to take the “I” off the fence (as it no longer has the choice of two Cells), and to put it into the Inner N.E. Cell, as in Diagram c.
This trouble may be saved by beginning with “No m are y”, as in Diagram b.
And now, when we take “Some m are x”, there is no fence to sit on! The “I” has to go, at once, into the N.E. Cell, as in Diagram c.
a
b
c
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
54/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
(3) “No x are m; All m are y”.
Here we begin by breaking up the Second into the two Propositions to which it is equivalent. Thus we have three Propositions to represent, viz.—
(1) “No x are m; (2) Some m are y; (3) No m are y”.
These we will take in the order 1, 3, 2.
First we take No. (1), viz. “No x are m”. This gives us Diagram a.
Adding to this, No. (3), viz. “No m are y”, we get Diagram b.
This time the “I”, representing No. (2), viz. “Some m are y,” has to sit on the fence, as there is no “O” to order it off! This gives us Diagram c.
a
b
c
pg052
(4) “All m are x; All y are m”.
Here we break up both Propositions, and thus get four to represent, viz.—
(1) “Some m are x; (2) No m are x;
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
55/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
(3) Some y are m; (4) No y are m”.
Symbolic Logic
These we will take in the order 2, 4, 1, 3.
First we take No. (2), viz. “No m are x”. This gives us Diagram a.
To this we add No. (4), viz. “No y are m”, and thus get Diagram b.
If we were to add to this No. (1), viz. “Some m are x”, we should have to put the “I” on a fence: so let us try No. (3) instead, viz. “Some y are m”. This gives us Diagram c.
And now there is no need to trouble about No. (1), as it would not add anything to our information to put a “I” on the fence. The Diagram already tells us that “Some m are x”.]
a
b
c
[Work Examples § 1, 912 (p. 97); § 2, 120 (p. 98).]
CHAPTER IV.
pg053
INTERPRETATION, IN TERMS OF x AND y, OF TRILITERAL DIAGRAM, WHEN MARKED WITH COUNTERS OR DIGITS.
The problem before us is, given a marked Triliteral Diagram, to ascertain what Propositions of Relation, in terms of x and y, are represented on it.
The best plan, for a beginner, is to draw a Biliteral Diagram alongside of it, and to transfer, from the one to the other, all the information he can. He can then read off, from the Biliteral Diagram, the required Propositions. After a little practice, he will be able to dispense with the Biliteral Diagram, and to read off the result from the Triliteral Diagram itself.
To transfer the information, observe the following Rules:—
(1) Examine the N.W. Quarter of the Triliteral Diagram. (2) If it contains a “I”, in either Cell, it is certainly occupied, and you may mark the
N.W. Quarter of the Biliteral Diagram with a “I”. (3) If it contains two “O”s, one in each Cell, it is certainly empty, and you may mark
the N.W. Quarter of the Biliteral Diagram with a “O”. (4) Deal in the same way with the N.E., the S.W., and the S.E. Quarter.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg054
56/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Let us take, as examples, the results of the four Examples worked in the previous Chapters.
(1)
In the N.W. Quarter, only one of the two Cells is marked as empty: so we do not know whether the N.W. Quarter of the Biliteral Diagram is occupied or empty: so we cannot mark it.
In the N.E. Quarter, we find two “O”s: so this Quarter is certainly empty; and we mark it so on the Biliteral Diagram.
In the S.W. Quarter, we have no information at all.
In the S.E. Quarter, we have not enough to use.
We may read off the result as “No x are y”, or “No y are x,” whichever we prefer.
(2)
In the N.W. Quarter, we have not enough information to use. In the N.E. Quarter, we find a “I”. This shows us that it is occupied: so we may mark the N.E. Quarter on the Biliteral Diagram with a “I”. In the S.W. Quarter, we have not enough information to use. In the S.E. Quarter, we have none at all.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
57/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
We may read off the result as “Some x are y”, or “Some y are x”, whichever we prefer.
(3)
pg055
In the N.W. Quarter, we have no information. (The “I”, sitting on the fence, is of no use to us until we know on which side he means to jump down!)
In the N.E. Quarter, we have not enough information to use.
Neither have we in the S.W. Quarter.
The S.E. Quarter is the only one that yields enough information to use. It is certainly empty: so we mark it as such on the Biliteral Diagram.
We may read off the results as “No x are y”, or “No y are x”, whichever we prefer.
(4)
The N.W. Quarter is occupied, in spite of the “O” in the Outer Cell. So we mark it with a “I” on the Biliteral Diagram.
The N.E. Quarter yields no information.
The S.W. Quarter is certainly empty. So we mark it as such on the Biliteral Diagram.
The S.E. Quarter does not yield enough information to use.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
58/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
We read off the result as “All y are x.”]
Symbolic Logic
[Review Tables V, VI (pp. 46, 47). Work Examples § 1, 13 16 (p. 97); § 2, 2132 (p. 98); § 3, 120 (p. 99).]
BOOK V.
SYLLOGISMS.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY
When a Trio of Biliteral Propositions of Relation is such that
(1) all their six Terms are Species of the same Genus, (2) every two of them contain between them a Pair of codivisional Classes, (3) the three Propositions are so related that, if the first two were true, the third would
be true,
the Trio is called a Syllogism; the Genus, of which each of the six Terms is a Species, is called its Universe of Discourse, or, more briefly, its Univ.; the first two Propositions are called its Premisses, and the third its Conclusion; also the Pair of codivisional Terms in the Premisses are called its Eliminands, and the other two its Retinends.
The Conclusion of a Syllogism is said to be consequent from its Premisses: hence it is usual to prefix to it the word “Therefore” (or the Symbol “∴”).
[Note that the Eliminands are so called because they are eliminated, and do not appear in the Conclusion; and that the Retinends are so called because they are retained, and do appear in the Conclusion.
Note also that the question, whether the Conclusion is or is not consequent from the Premisses, is not affected by the actual truth or falsity of any of the Trio, but depends entirely on their relationship to each other.
As a specimen-Syllogism, let us take the Trio
“No x-Things are m-Things; No y-Things are m-Things.
No x-Things are y-Things.”
which we may write, as explained at p. 26, thus:—
“No x are m; No y are m.
No x are y”.
Here the first and second contain the Pair of codivisional Classes m and m; the first and third contain the Pair x and x; and the second and third contain the Pair y and y.
Also the three Propositions are (as we shall see hereafter) so related that, if the first two were true, the third would also be true.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg056 pg057
59/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Hence the Trio is a Syllogism; the two Propositions, “No x are m” and “No y are m”, are its Premisses; the Proposition “No x are y” is its Conclusion; the Terms m and m are its Eliminands; and the Terms x and y are its Retinends.
Hence we may write it thus:—
“No x are m; No y are m. ∴ No x are y”.
As a second specimen, let us take the Trio
“All cats understand French; Some chickens are cats.
Some chickens understand French”.
These, put into normal form, are
“All cats are creatures understanding French; Some chickens are cats.
Some chickens are creatures understanding French”.
Here all the six Terms are Species of the Genus “creatures.”
Also the first and second Propositions contain the Pair of codivisional Classes “cats” and “cats”; the first and third contain the Pair “creatures understanding French” and “creatures understanding French”; and the second and third contain the Pair “chickens” and “chickens”.
Also the three Propositions are (as we shall see at p. 64) so related that, if the first two were true, the third would be true. (The first two are, as it happens, not strictly true in our planet. But there is nothing to hinder them from being true in some other planet, say Mars or Jupiter—in which case the third would also be true in that planet, and its inhabitants would probably engage chickens as nurserygovernesses. They would thus secure a singular contingent privilege, unknown in England, namely, that they would be able, at any time when provisions ran short, to utilise the nursery-governess for the nursery-dinner!)
Hence the Trio is a Syllogism; the Genus “creatures” is its Univ.; the two Propositions, “All cats understand French“ and ”Some chickens are cats”, are its Premisses, the Proposition “Some chickens understand French” is its Conclusion; the Terms “cats” and “cats” are its Eliminands; and the Terms, “creatures understanding French” and “chickens”, are its Retinends.
Hence we may write it thus:—
“All cats understand French; Some chickens are cats; ∴ Some chickens understand French”.]
CHAPTER II.
PROBLEMS IN SYLLOGISMS.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
§ 1.
pg058
pg059
60/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Introductory.
When the Terms of a Proposition are represented by words, it is said to be concrete; when by letters, abstract.
To translate a Proposition from concrete into abstract form, we fix on a Univ., and regard each Term as a Species of it, and we choose a letter to represent its Differentia.
[For example, suppose we wish to translate “Some soldiers are brave” into abstract form. We may take “men” as Univ., and regard “soldiers” and “brave men” as Species of the Genus “men”; and we may choose x to represent the peculiar Attribute (say “military”) of “soldiers,” and y to represent “brave.” Then the Proposition may be written “Some military men are brave men”; i.e. “Some x-men are y-men”; i.e. (omitting “men,” as explained at p. 26) “Some x are y.”
In practice, we should merely say “Let Univ. be “men”, x = soldiers, y = brave”, and at once translate “Some soldiers are brave” into “Some x are y.”]
The Problems we shall have to solve are of two kinds, viz.
(1) “Given a Pair of Propositions of Relation, which contain between them a pair of codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as Premisses: to ascertain what Conclusion, if any, is consequent from them.”
(2) “Given a Trio of Propositions of Relation, of which every two contain a pair of codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as a Syllogism: to ascertain whether the proposed Conclusion is consequent from the proposed Premisses, and, if so, whether it is complete.”
These Problems we will discuss separately.
§ 2.
pg060
Given a Pair of Propositions of Relation, which contain between them a pair of codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as Premisses: to ascertain what Conclusion,
if any, is consequent from them.
The Rules, for doing this, are as follows:—
(1) Determine the Universe of Discourse.
(2) Construct a Dictionary, making m and m (or m and m) represent the pair of codivisional Classes, and x (or x) and y (or y) the other two.
(3) Translate the proposed Premisses into abstract form.
(4) Represent them, together, on a Triliteral Diagram.
(5) Ascertain what Proposition, if any, in terms of x and y, is also represented on it.
(6) Translate this into concrete form.
It is evident that, if the proposed Premisses were true, this other Proposition would also be true. Hence it is a Conclusion consequent from the proposed Premisses.
[Let us work some examples.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
61/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
(1) “No son of mine is dishonest; People always treat an honest man with respect”.
Taking “men” as Univ., we may write these as follows:—
“No sons of mine are dishonest men; All honest men are men treated with respect”.
We can now construct our Dictionary, viz. m = honest; x = sons of mine; y = treated with respect.
(Note that the expression “x = sons of mine” is an abbreviated form of “x = the Differentia of sons of mine, when regarded as a Species of men”.)
The next thing is to translate the proposed Premisses into abstract form, as follows: —
“No x are m; All m are y”.
Next, by the process described at p. 50, we represent these on a Triliteral Diagram, thus: —
Next, by the process described at p. 53, we transfer to a Biliteral Diagram all the information we can.
The result we read as “No x are y” or as “No y are x,” whichever we prefer. So we refer to our Dictionary, to see which will look best; and we choose
“No x are y”,
which, translated into concrete form, is
“No son of mine fails to be treated with respect”.
(2) “All cats understand French; Some chickens are cats”.
Taking “creatures” as Univ., we write these as follows:—
“All cats are creatures understanding French; Some chickens are cats”.
We can now construct our Dictionary, viz. m = cats; x = understanding French; y = chickens.
The proposed Premisses, translated into abstract form, are
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg061
62/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“All m are x; Some y are m”.
Symbolic Logic
In order to represent these on a Triliteral Diagram, we break up the first into the two Propositions to which it is equivalent, and thus get the three Propositions
(1) “Some m are x; (2) No m are x; (3) Some y are m”.
The Rule, given at p. 50, would make us take these in the order 2, 1, 3.
This, however, would produce the result
So it would be better to take them in the order 2, 3, 1. Nos. (2) and (3) give us the result here shown; and now we need not trouble about No. (1), as the Proposition “Some m are x” is already represented on the Diagram.
Transferring our information to a Biliteral Diagram, we get
This result we can read either as “Some x are y” or “Some y are x”.
After consulting our Dictionary, we choose
“Some y are x”,
which, translated into concrete form, is
“Some chickens understand French.”
(3) “All diligent students are successful; All ignorant students are unsuccessful”.
Let Univ. be “students”; m = successful; x = diligent; y = ignorant.
These Premisses, in abstract form, are
“All x are m; All y are m”.
These, broken up, give us the four Propositions
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg062
63/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
(1) “Some x are m; (2) No x are m; (3) Some y are m; (4) No y are m”.
Symbolic Logic
which we will take in the order 2, 4, 1, 3.
Representing these on a Triliteral Diagram, we get
And this information, transferred to a Biliteral Diagram, is
Here we get two Conclusions, viz.
“All x are y; All y are x.”
And these, translated into concrete form, are
“All diligent students are (not-ignorant, i.e.) learned; All ignorant students are (not-diligent, i.e.) idle”. (See p. 4.)
(4)
“Of the prisoners who were put on their trial at the last Assizes, all, against whom the verdict guilty was returned, were sentenced to imprisonment;
Some, who were sentenced to imprisonment, were also sentenced to hard labour”.
Let Univ. be “the prisoners who were put on their trial at the last Assizes”; m = who were sentenced to imprisonment; x = against whom the verdict guilty was returned; y = who were sentenced to hard labour.
The Premisses, translated into abstract form, are
“All x are m; Some m are y”.
Breaking up the first, we get the three
(1) “Some x are m; (2) No x are m; (3) Some m are y”.
Representing these, in the order 2, 1, 3, on a Triliteral Diagram, we get
Here we get no Conclusion at all.
You would very likely have guessed, if you had seen only the Premisses, that the Conclusion would be
pg063
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
64/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
“Some, against whom the verdict guilty was returned, were sentenced to hard labour”.
But this Conclusion is not even true, with regard to the Assizes I have here invented.
“Not true!” you exclaim. “Then who were they, who were sentenced to imprisonment and were also sentenced to hard labour? They must have had the verdict guilty returned against them, or how could they be sentenced?”
Well, it happened like this, you see. They were three ruffians, who had committed highway-robbery. When they were put on their trial, they pleaded guilty. So no verdict was returned at all; and they were sentenced at once.]
I will now work out, in their briefest form, as models for the Reader to imitate in working examples, the above four concrete Problems.
(1) [see p. 60] “No son of mine is dishonest; People always treat an honest man with respect.”
Univ. “men”; m = honest; x = my sons; y = treated with respect.
pg064
“No x are m; All m are y.”
∴ “No x are y.”
i.e. “No son of mine ever fails to be treated with respect.”
“All cats understand French; Some chickens are cats”.
(2) [see p. 61]
Univ. “creatures”; m = cats; x = understanding French; y = chickens.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
65/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“All m are x; Some y are m.”
Symbolic Logic
∴ “Some y are x.”
i.e. “Some chickens understand French.” (3) [see p. 62]
“All diligent students are successful; All ignorant students are unsuccessful”. Univ. “students”; m = successful; x = diligent; y = ignorant.
“All x are m; All y are m.”
∴ “All x are y; All y are x.”
i.e. “All diligent students are learned; and all ignorant students are idle”.
(4) [see p. 63] “Of the prisoners who were put on their trial at the last Assizes, all, against whom the verdict guilty was returned, were sentenced to imprisonment;
Some, who were sentenced to imprisonment, were also sentenced to hard labour”.
Univ. “prisoners who were put on their trial at the last Assizes”, m = sentenced to imprisonment; x = against whom the verdict guilty was returned; y = sentenced to hard labour.
pg065
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
66/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“All x are m; Some m are y.”
Symbolic Logic
There is no Conclusion.
[Review Tables VII, VIII (pp. 48, 49). Work Examples § 1, 1721 (p. 97); § 4, 16 (p. 100); § 5, 16 (p. 101).]
§ 3.
pg066
Given a Trio of Propositions of Relation, of which every two contain a Pair of codivisional Classes, and which are proposed as a Syllogism; to ascertain whether the proposed Conclusion is consequent from the proposed Premisses, and, if so, whether it is
complete.
The Rules, for doing this, are as follows:—
(1) Take the proposed Premisses, and ascertain, by the process described at p. 60, what Conclusion, if any, is consequent from them.
(2) If there be no Conclusion, say so.
(3) If there be a Conclusion, compare it with the proposed Conclusion, and pronounce accordingly.
I will now work out, in their briefest form, as models for the Reader to imitate in working examples, six Problems.
(1) “All soldiers are strong; All soldiers are brave.
Some strong men are brave.”
Univ. “men”; m = soldiers; x = strong; y = brave.
“All m are x; All m are y.
Some x are y.”
pg067
∴ “Some x are y.”
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
67/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Hence proposed Conclusion is right.
Symbolic Logic
(2)
“I admire these pictures; When I admire anything I wish to examine it thoroughly.
I wish to examine some of these pictures thoroughly.”
Univ. “things”; m = admired by me; x = these pictures; y = things which I wish to examine thoroughly.
“All x are m; All m are y.
Some x are y.”
∴ “All x are y.”
Hence proposed Conclusion is incomplete, the complete one being “I wish to examine all these pictures thoroughly”.
(3) “None but the brave deserve the fair; Some braggarts are cowards.
Some braggarts do not deserve the fair.” Univ. “persons”; m = brave; x = deserving of the fair; y = braggarts.
“No m are x; Some y are m. Some y are x.”
∴ “Some y are x.”
Hence proposed Conclusion is right.
(4) “All soldiers can march; Some babies are not soldiers.
Some babies cannot march”.
Univ. “persons”; m = soldiers; x = able to march; y = babies.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg068
68/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“All m are x; Some y are m. Some y are x.”
Symbolic Logic
There is no Conclusion.
(5) “All selfish men are unpopular; All obliging men are popular.
All obliging men are unselfish”. Univ. “men”; m = popular; x = selfish; y = obliging.
“All x are m; All y are m. All y are x.”
∴ “All x are y; All y are x.”
Hence proposed Conclusion is incomplete, the complete one containing, in addition, “All selfish men are disobliging”.
(6) ”No one, who means to go by the train and cannot get a conveyance, and has not enough time to walk to the station, can do without running;
This party of tourists mean to go by the train and cannot get a conveyance, but they have plenty of time to walk to the station.
This party of tourists need not run.”
Univ. “persons meaning to go by the train, and unable to get a conveyance”; m = having enough time to walk to the station; x = needing to run; y = these tourists.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
69/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
“No m are x; All y are m. All y are x.”
Symbolic Logic
There is no Conclusion.
pg069
[Here is another opportunity, gentle Reader, for playing a trick on your innocent friend. Put the proposed Syllogism before him, and ask him what he thinks of the Conclusion.
He will reply “Why, its perfectly correct, of course! And if your precious Logicbook tells you it isnt, dont believe it! You dont mean to tell me those tourists need to run? If I were one of them, and knew the Premisses to be true, I should be quite clear that I neednt run—and I should walk!”
And you will reply “But suppose there was a mad bull behind you?”
And then your innocent friend will say “Hum! Ha! I must think that over a bit!”
You may then explain to him, as a convenient test of the soundness of a Syllogism, that, if circumstances can be invented which, without interfering with the truth of the Premisses, would make the Conclusion false, the Syllogism must be unsound.]
[Review Tables VVIII (pp. 4649). Work Examples § 4, 712 (p. 100); § 5, 712 (p. 101); § 6, 110 (p. 106); § 7, 16 (pp. 107, 108).]
BOOK VI.
pg070
THE METHOD OF SUBSCRIPTS.
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
Let us agree that “x1” shall mean “Some existing Things have the Attribute x”, i.e. (more briefly) “Some x exist”; also that “xy1” shall mean “Some xy exist”, and so on. Such a Proposition may be called an Entity.
[Note that, when there are two letters in the expression, it does not in the least matter which stands first: “xy1” and “yx1” mean exactly the same.]
Also that “x0” shall mean “No existing Things have the Attribute x”, i.e. (more briefly) “No x exist”; also that “xy0” shall mean “No xy exist”, and so on. Such a Proposition may be called a Nullity.
Also that “†” shall mean “and”.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
70/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Thus “ab1 † cd0” means “Some ab exist and no cd exist”.]
Also that “¶” shall mean “would, if true, prove”.
[Thus, “x0 ¶ xy0” means “The Proposition No x exist would, if true, prove the Proposition No xy exist”.]
When two Letters are both of them accented, or both not accented, they are said to have Like Signs, or to be Like: when one is accented, and the other not, they are said to have Unlike Signs, or to be Unlike.
CHAPTER II.
pg071
REPRESENTATION OF PROPOSITIONS OF RELATION.
Let us take, first, the Proposition “Some x are y”.
This, we know, is equivalent to the Proposition of Existence “Some xy exist”. (See p. 31.) Hence it may be represented by the expression “xy1”.
The Converse Proposition “Some y are x” may of course be represented by the same expression, viz. “xy1”.
Similarly we may represent the three similar Pairs of Converse Propositions, viz.—
“Some x are y” = “Some y are x”, “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”, “Some x are y” = “Some y are x”.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “No x are y”.
This, we know, is equivalent to the Proposition of Existence “No xy exist”. (See p. 33.) Hence it may be represented by the expression “xy0”.
The Converse Proposition “No y are x” may of course be represented by the same expression, viz. “xy0”.
Similarly we may represent the three similar Pairs of Converse Propositions, viz.—
“No x are y” = “No y are x”, “No x are y” = “No y are x”, “No x are y” = “No y are x”.
Let us take, next, the Proposition “All x are y”.
Now it is evident that the Double Proposition of Existence “Some x exist and no xy exist” tells us that some x-Things exist, but that none of them have the Attribute y: that is, it tells us that all of them have the Attribute y: that is, it tells us that “All x are y”.
Also it is evident that the expression “x1 † xy0” represents this Double Proposition.
Hence it also represents the Proposition “All x are y”.
pg072
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
71/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[The Reader will perhaps be puzzled by the statement that the Proposition “All x are y” is equivalent to the Double Proposition “Some x exist and no xy exist,” remembering that it was stated, at p. 33, to be equivalent to the Double Proposition “Some x are y and no x are y” (i.e. “Some xy exist and no xy exist”). The explanation is that the Proposition “Some xy exist” contains superfluous information. “Some x exist” is enough for our purpose.]
This expression may be written in a shorter form, viz. “x1y0”, since each Subscript takes effect back to the beginning of the expression.
Similarly we may represent the seven similar Propositions “All x are y”, “All x are y”, “All x are y”, “All y are x”, “All y are x”, “All y are x”, and “All y are x”.
[The Reader should make out all these for himself.]
It will be convenient to remember that, in translating a Proposition, beginning with “All”, from abstract form into subscript form, or vice versâ, the Predicate changes sign (that is, changes from positive to negative, or else from negative to positive).
[Thus, the Proposition “All y are x” becomes “y1x0”, where the Predicate changes from x to x.
Again, the expression “x1y0” becomes “All x are y”, where the Predicate changes for y to y.]
CHAPTER III.
pg073
SYLLOGISMS.
§ 1.
Representation of Syllogisms.
We already know how to represent each of the three Propositions of a Syllogism in subscript form. When that is done, all we need, besides, is to write the three expressions in a row, with “†” between the Premisses, and “¶” before the Conclusion.
[Thus the Syllogism
“No x are m; All m are y.
∴ No x are y.”
may be represented thus:—
xm0 † m1y0 ¶ xy0
When a Proposition has to be translated from concrete form into subscript form, the Reader will find it convenient, just at first, to translate it into abstract form, and thence into subscript form. But, after a little practice, he will find it quite easy to go straight from concrete form to subscript form.]
§ 2.
pg074
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
72/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Formulæ for solving Problems in Syllogisms.
When once we have found, by Diagrams, the Conclusion to a given Pair of Premisses, and have represented the Syllogism in subscript form, we have a Formula, by which we can at once find, without having to use Diagrams again, the Conclusion to any other Pair of Premisses having the same subscript forms.
[Thus, the expression
xm0 † ym0 ¶ xy0
is a Formula, by which we can find the Conclusion to any Pair of Premisses whose subscript forms are
xm0 † ym0
For example, suppose we had the Pair of Propositions
“No gluttons are healthy; No unhealthy men are strong”.
proposed as Premisses. Taking “men” as our Universe, and making m = healthy; x = gluttons; y = strong; we might translate the Pair into abstract form, thus:—
“No x are m; No m are y”.
These, in subscript form, would be
xm0 † my0
which are identical with those in our Formula. Hence we at once know the Conclusion to be
xy0
that is, in abstract form,
“No x are y”;
that is, in concrete form,
“No gluttons are strong”.]
I shall now take three different forms of Pairs of Premisses, and work out their Conclusions, once for all, by Diagrams; and thus obtain some useful Formulæ. I shall call them “Fig. I”, “Fig. II”, and “Fig. III”.
Fig. I.
pg075
This includes any Pair of Premisses which are both of them Nullities, and which contain Unlike Eliminands.
The simplest case is
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
73/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
xm0 † ym0
Symbolic Logic
∴ xy0
In this case we see that the Conclusion is a Nullity, and that the Retinends have kept their Signs.
And we should find this Rule to hold good with any Pair of Premisses which fulfil the given conditions.
[The Reader had better satisfy himself of this, by working out, on Diagrams, several varieties, such as
m1x0 † ym0 (which ¶ xy0) xm0 † m1y0 (which ¶ xy0) xm0 † ym0 (which ¶ xy0) m1x0 † m1y0 (which ¶ xy0).]
If either Retinend is asserted in the Premisses to exist, of course it may be so asserted in the Conclusion.
Hence we get two Variants of Fig. I, viz.
(α) where one Retinend is so asserted;
(β) where both are so asserted.
[The Reader had better work out, on Diagrams, examples of these two Variants, such as
m1x0 † y1m0 (which proves y1x0) x1m0 † m1y0 (which proves x1y0) x1m0 † y1m0 (which proves x1y0 † y1x0).]
The Formula, to be remembered, is
xm0 † ym0 ¶ xy0
with the following two Rules:—
(1) Two Nullities, with Unlike Eliminands, yield a Nullity, in which both Retinends keep their Signs.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
74/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
(2) A Retinend, asserted in the Premisses to exist, may be so asserted in the Conclusion.
[Note that Rule (1) is merely the Formula expressed in words.]
Fig. II.
This includes any Pair of Premisses, of which one is a Nullity and the other an Entity, and which contain Like Eliminands.
The simplest case is
xm0 † ym1
pg076
∴ xy1
In this case we see that the Conclusion is an Entity, and that the Nullity-Retinend has changed its Sign.
And we should find this Rule to hold good with any Pair of Premisses which fulfil the given conditions.
[The Reader had better satisfy himself of this, by working out, on Diagrams, several varieties, such as
xm0 † ym1 (which ¶ xy1) x1m0 † ym1 (which ¶ xy1) m1x0 † ym1 (which ¶ xy1).]
The Formula, to be remembered, is,
xm0 † ym1 ¶ xy1
with the following Rule:—
A Nullity and an Entity, with Like Eliminands, yield an Entity, in which the NullityRetinend changes its Sign.
[Note that this Rule is merely the Formula expressed in words.]
Fig. III.
pg077
This includes any Pair of Premisses which are both of them Nullities, and which contain Like Eliminands asserted to exist.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
75/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
The simplest case is
Symbolic Logic
xm0 † ym0 † m1
[Note that “m1” is here stated separately, because it does not matter in which of the two Premisses it occurs: so that this includes the three forms “m1x0 † ym0”, “xm0 † m1y0”, and “m1x0 † m1y0”.]
∴ xy1
In this case we see that the Conclusion is an Entity, and that both Retinends have changed their Signs.
And we should find this Rule to hold good with any Pair of Premisses which fulfil the given conditions.
[The Reader had better satisfy himself of this, by working out, on Diagrams, several varieties, such as
xm0 † m1y0 (which ¶ xy1) m1x0 † my0 (which ¶ xy1) m1x0 † m1y0 (which ¶ xy1).]
The Formula, to be remembered, is
xm0 † ym0 † m1 ¶ xy1
with the following Rule (which is merely the Formula expressed in words):—
Two Nullities, with Like Eliminands asserted to exist, yield an Entity, in which both Retinends change their Signs.
In order to help the Reader to remember the peculiarities and Formulæ of these three Figures, I will put them all together in one Table.
TABLE IX.
Fig. I. xm0 † ym0 ¶ xy0
pg078
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
76/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
Two Nullities, with Unlike Eliminands, yield a Nullity, in which both Retinends keep their Signs.
A Retinend, asserted in the Premisses to exist, may be so asserted in the Conclusion.
Fig. II.
xm0 † ym1 ¶ xy1
A Nullity and an Entity, with Like Eliminands, yield an Entity, in which the NullityRetinend changes its Sign.
Fig. III.
xm0 † ym0 † m1 ¶ xy1
Two Nullities, with Like Eliminands asserted to exist, yield an Entity, in which both Retinends change their Signs.
I will now work out, by these Formulæ, as models for the Reader to imitate, some Problems in Syllogisms which have been already worked, by Diagrams, in Book V., Chap. II.
(1) [see p. 64]
“No son of mine is dishonest; People always treat an honest man with respect.”
Univ. “men”; m = honest; x = my sons; y = treated with respect.
xm0 † m1y0 ¶ xy0 [Fig. I.
i.e. “No son of mine ever fails to be treated with respect.”
“All cats understand French; Some chickens are cats.”
(2) [see p. 64]
pg079
Univ. “creatures”; m = cats; x = understanding French; y = chickens.
m1x0 † ym1 ¶ xy1 [Fig. II.
i.e. “Some chickens understand French.”
(3) [see p. 64]
“All diligent students are successful; All ignorant students are unsuccessful.”
Univ. “students”; m = successful; x = diligent; y = ignorant.
x1m0 † y1m0 ¶ x1y0 † y1x0 [Fig. I (β).
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
77/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
i.e. “All diligent students are learned; and all ignorant students are idle.”
(4) [see p. 66]
“All soldiers are strong; All soldiers are brave.
Some strong men are brave.”
Univ. “men”; m = soldiers; x = strong; y = brave.
m1x0 † m1y0 ¶ xy1 [Fig. III.
Hence proposed Conclusion is right.
(5) [see p. 67]
“I admire these pictures; When I admire anything, I wish to examine it thoroughly.
I wish to examine some of these pictures thoroughly.”
Univ. “things”; m = admired by me; x = these; y = things which I wish to examine thoroughly.
x1m0 † m1y0 ¶ x1y0 [Fig. I (α).
Hence proposed Conclusion, xy1, is incomplete, the complete one being “I wish to examine all these pictures thoroughly.”
(6) [see p. 67]
“None but the brave deserve the fair; Some braggarts are cowards.
Some braggarts do not deserve the fair.”
pg080
Univ. “persons”; m = brave; x = deserving of the fair; y = braggarts.
mx0 † ym1 ¶ xy1 [Fig. II.
Hence proposed Conclusion is right.
(7) [see p. 69]
”No one, who means to go by the train and cannot get a conveyance, and has not enough time to walk to the station, can do without running; This party of tourists mean to go by the train and cannot get a conveyance, but they have plenty of time to walk to the station.
This party of tourists need not run.”
Univ. “persons meaning to go by the train, and unable to get a conveyance”; m = having enough time to walk to the station; x = needing to run; y = these tourists.
mx0 † y1m0 do not come under any of the three Figures. Hence it is necessary to return to the Method of Diagrams, as shown at p. 69.
Hence there is no Conclusion.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
78/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[Work Examples § 4, 1220 (p. 100); § 5, 1324 (pp. 101, 102); § 6, 16 (p. 106); § 7, 13 (pp. 107, 108). Also read Note (A), at p. 164.]
§ 3.
pg081
Fallacies.
Any argument which deceives us, by seeming to prove what it does not really prove, may be called a Fallacy (derived from the Latin verb fallo “I deceive”): but the particular kind, to be now discussed, consists of a Pair of Propositions, which are proposed as the Premisses of a Syllogism, but yield no Conclusion.
When each of the proposed Premisses is a Proposition in I, or E, or A, (the only kinds with which we are now concerned,) the Fallacy may be detected by the Method of Diagrams, by simply setting them out on a Triliteral Diagram, and observing that they yield no information which can be transferred to the Biliteral Diagram.
But suppose we were working by the Method of Subscripts, and had to deal with a Pair of proposed Premisses, which happened to be a Fallacy, how could we be certain that they would not yield any Conclusion?
Our best plan is, I think, to deal with Fallacies in the same was as we have already dealt with Syllogisms: that is, to take certain forms of Pairs of Propositions, and to work them out, once for all, on the Triliteral Diagram, and ascertain that they yield no Conclusion; and then to record them, for future use, as Formulæ for Fallacies, just as we have already recorded our three Formulæ for Syllogisms.
pg082
Now, if we were to record the two Sets of Formulæ in the same shape, viz. by the Method of Subscripts, there would be considerable risk of confusing the two kinds. Hence, in order to keep them distinct, I propose to record the Formulæ for Fallacies in words, and to call them “Forms” instead of “Formulæ.”
Let us now proceed to find, by the Method of Diagrams, three “Forms of Fallacies,” which we will then put on record for future use. They are as follows:—
(1) Fallacy of Like Eliminands not asserted to exist. (2) Fallacy of Unlike Eliminands with an Entity-Premiss. (3) Fallacy of two Entity-Premisses.
These shall be discussed separately, and it will be seen that each fails to yield a Conclusion.
(1) Fallacy of Like Eliminands not asserted to exist.
It is evident that neither of the given Propositions can be an Entity, since that kind asserts the existence of both of its Terms (see p. 20). Hence they must both be Nullities.
Hence the given Pair may be represented by (xm0 † ym0), with or without x1, y1.
These, set out on Triliteral Diagrams, are
xm0 † ym0
x1m0 † ym0
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
79/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
xm0 † y1m0
x1m0 † y1m0
(2) Fallacy of Unlike Eliminands with an Entity-Premiss.
Here the given Pair may be represented by (xm0 † ym1) with or without x1 or m1.
These, set out on Triliteral Diagrams, are
xm0 † ym1
x1m0 † ym1
m1x0 † ym1
pg083
(3) Fallacy of two Entity-Premisses.
Here the given Pair may be represented by either (xm1 † ym1) or (xm1 † ym1).
These, set out on Triliteral Diagrams, are
xm1 † ym1
xm1 † ym1
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
80/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
§ 4.
pg084
Method of proceeding with a given Pair of Propositions.
Let us suppose that we have before us a Pair of Propositions of Relation, which contain between them a Pair of codivisional Classes, and that we wish to ascertain what Conclusion, if any, is consequent from them. We translate them, if necessary, into subscript-form, and then proceed as follows:—
(1) We examine their Subscripts, in order to see whether they are
(a) a Pair of Nullities; or (b) a Nullity and an Entity; or (c) a Pair of Entities.
(2) If they are a Pair of Nullities, we examine their Eliminands, in order to see whether they are Unlike or Like.
If their Eliminands are Unlike, it is a case of Fig. I. We then examine their Retinends, to see whether one or both of them are asserted to exist. If one Retinend is so asserted, it is a case of Fig. I (α); if both, it is a case of Fig. I (β).
If their Eliminands are Like, we examine them, in order to see whether either of them is asserted to exist. If so, it is a case of Fig. III.; if not, it is a case of “Fallacy of Like Eliminands not asserted to exist.”
(3) If they are a Nullity and an Entity, we examine their Eliminands, in order to see whether they are Like or Unlike.
If their Eliminands are Like, it is a case of Fig. II.; if Unlike, it is a case of “Fallacy of Unlike Eliminands with an Entity-Premiss.”
(4) If they are a Pair of Entities, it is a case of “Fallacy of two Entity-Premisses.”
[Work Examples § 4, 111 (p. 100); § 5, 112 (p. 101); § 6, 712 (p. 106); § 7, 7 12 (p. 108).]
BOOK VII.
SORITESES.
pg085
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
81/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
CHAPTER I.
INTRODUCTORY.
When a Set of three or more Biliteral Propositions are such that all their Terms are Species of the same Genus, and are also so related that two of them, taken together, yield a Conclusion, which, taken with another of them, yields another Conclusion, and so on, until all have been taken, it is evident that, if the original Set were true, the last Conclusion would also be true.
Such a Set, with the last Conclusion tacked on, is called a Sorites; the original Set of Propositions is called its Premisses; each of the intermediate Conclusions is called a Partial Conclusion of the Sorites; the last Conclusion is called its Complete Conclusion, or, more briefly, its Conclusion; the Genus, of which all the Terms are Species, is called its Universe of Discourse, or, more briefly, its Univ.; the Terms, used as Eliminands in the Syllogisms, are called its Eliminands; and the two Terms, which are retained, and therefore appear in the Conclusion, are called its Retinends.
[Note that each Partial Conclusion contains one or two Eliminands; but that the Complete Conclusion contains Retinends only.]
The Conclusion is said to be consequent from the Premisses; for which reason it is usual to prefix to it the word “Therefore” (or the symbol “∴”).
[Note that the question, whether the Conclusion is or is not consequent from the Premisses, is not affected by the actual truth or falsity of any one of the Propositions which make up the Sorites, by depends entirely on their relationship to one another.
As a specimen-Sorites, let us take the following Set of 5 Propositions:—
pg086
(1) ”No a are b; (2) All b are c; (3) All c are d; (4) No e are a; (5) All h are e”.
Here the first and second, taken together, yield “No a are c”.
This, taken along with the third, yields “No a are d”.
This, taken along with the fourth, yields “No d are e”.
And this, taken along with the fifth, yields “All h are d”.
Hence, if the original Set were true, this would also be true.
Hence the original Set, with this tacked on, is a Sorites; the original Set is its Premisses; the Proposition “All h are d” is its Conclusion; the Terms a, b, c, e are its Eliminands; and the Terms d and h are its Retinends.
Hence we may write the whole Sorites thus:—
”No a are b; All b are c;
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
82/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
All c are d; No e are a; All h are e.
∴ All h are d”.
Symbolic Logic
In the above Sorites, the 3 Partial Conclusions are the Positions “No a are e”, “No a are d”, “No d are e”; but, if the Premisses were arranged in other ways, other Partial Conclusions might be obtained. Thus, the order 41523 yields the Partial Conclusions “No c are b”, “All h are b”, “All h are c”. There are altogether nine Partial Conclusions to this Sorites, which the Reader will find it an interesting task to make out for himself.]
CHAPTER II.
PROBLEMS IN SORITESES.
§ 1.
Introductory.
The Problems we shall have to solve are of the following form:—
“Given three or more Propositions of Relation, which are proposed as Premisses: to ascertain what Conclusion, if any, is consequent from them.”
We will limit ourselves, at present, to Problems which can be worked by the Formulæ of Fig. I. (See p. 75.) Those, that require other Formulæ, are rather too hard for beginners.
Such Problems may be solved by either of two Methods, viz.
(1) The Method of Separate Syllogisms; (2) The Method of Underscoring.
These shall be discussed separately.
§ 2.
Solution by Method of Separate Syllogisms.
The Rules, for doing this, are as follows:—
(1) Name the Universe of Discourse. (2) Construct a Dictionary, making a, b, c, &c. represent the Terms. (3) Put the Proposed Premisses into subscript form. (4) Select two which, containing between them a pair of codivisional Classes, can be used as the Premisses of a Syllogism. (5) Find their Conclusion by Formula. (6) Find a third Premiss which, along with this Conclusion, can be used as the Premisses of a second Syllogism. (7) Find a second Conclusion by Formula. (8) Proceed thus, until all the proposed Premisses have been used. (9) Put the last Conclusion, which is the Complete Conclusion of the Sorites, into concrete form.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg087 pg088
83/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[As an example of this process, let us take, as the proposed Set of Premisses,
(1) “All the policemen on this beat sup with our cook; (2) No man with long hair can fail to be a poet; (3) Amos Judd has never been in prison; (4) Our cooks cousins all love cold mutton; (5) None but policemen on this beat are poets; (6) None but her cousins ever sup with our cook; (7) Men with short hair have all been in prison.”
Univ. “men”; a = Amos Judd; b = cousins of our cook; c = having been in prison; d = long-haired; e = loving cold mutton; h = poets; k = policemen on this beat; l = supping with our cook
We now have to put the proposed Premisses into subscript form. Let us begin by putting them into abstract form. The result is
(1) ”All k are l; (2) No d are h; (3) All a are c; (4) All b are e; (5) No k are h; (6) No b are l; (7) All d are c.”
And it is now easy to put them into subscript form, as follows:—
(1) k1l0 (2) dh0 (3) a1c0 (4) b1e0 (5) kh0 (6) bl0 (7) d1c0
We now have to find a pair of Premisses which will yield a Conclusion. Let us begin with No. (1), and look down the list, till we come to one which we can take along with it, so as to form Premisses belonging to Fig. I. We find that No. (5) will do, since we can take k as our Eliminand. So our first syllogism is
(1) k1l0 (5) kh0
∴ lh0 … (8)
We must now begin again with lh0 and find a Premiss to go along with it. We find that No. (2) will do, h being our Eliminand. So our next Syllogism is
(8) lh0 (2) dh0
∴ ld0 … (9)
pg089
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
84/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
We have now used up Nos. (1), (5), and (2), and must search among the others for a partner for ld0. We find that No. (6) will do. So we write
(9) ld0 (6) bl0
∴ db0 … (10)
Now what can we take along with db0? No. (4) will do.
(10) db0 (4) b1e0
∴ de0 … (11)
Along with this we may take No. (7).
(11) de0 (7) d1c0
∴ ce0 … (12)
And along with this we may take No. (3).
(12) ce0 (3) a1c0
∴ a1e0
This Complete Conclusion, translated into abstract form, is
“All a are e”;
and this, translated into concrete form, is
“Amos Judd loves cold mutton.”
In actually working this Problem, the above explanations would, of course, be omitted, and all, that would appear on paper, would be as follows:—
(1) k1l0 (2) dh0 (3) a1c0 (4) b1e0 (5) kh0 (6) bl0 (7) d1c0
(1) k1l0 (5) kh0
∴ lh0 … (8)
(8) lh0 (2) dh0
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg090
85/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
∴ ld0 … (9)
Symbolic Logic
(9) ld0 (6) bl0
∴ db0 … (10)
(10) db0 (4) b1e0
∴ de0 … (11)
(11) de0 (7) d1c0
∴ ce0 … (12)
(12) ce0 (3) a1c0
∴ a1e0
Note that, in working a Sorites by this Process, we may begin with any Premiss we choose.]
§ 3.
pg091
Solution by Method of Underscoring.
Consider the Pair of Premisses
xm0 † ym0
which yield the Conclusion xy0
We see that, in order to get this Conclusion, we must eliminate m and m, and write x and y together in one expression.
Now, if we agree to mark m and m as eliminated, and to read the two expressions together, as if they were written in one, the two Premisses will then exactly represent the Conclusion, and we need not write it out separately.
Let us agree to mark the eliminated letters by underscoring them, putting a single score under the first, and a double one under the second.
The two Premisses now become
xm0 † ym0
which we read as “xy0”.
In copying out the Premisses for underscoring, it will be convenient to omit all subscripts. As to the “0s” we may always suppose them written, and, as to the “1s”, we are not concerned to know which Terms are asserted to exist, except those which appear in the Complete Conclusion; and for them it will be easy enough to refer to the original list.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
86/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
[I will now go through the process of solving, by this method, the example worked in § 2.
The Data are
1 2 3 4 56 7 k1l0 † dh0 † a1c0 † b1e0 † kh0 † bl0 † d1c0
The Reader should take a piece of paper, and write out this solution for himself. The first line will consist of the above Data; the second must be composed, bit by bit, according to the following directions.
We begin by writing down the first Premiss, with its numeral over it, but omitting the subscripts.
We have now to find a Premiss which can be combined with this, i.e., a Premiss containing either k or l. The first we find is No. 5; and this we tack on, with a †.
To get the Conclusion from these, k and k must be eliminated, and what remains must be taken as one expression. So we underscore them, putting a single score under k, and a double one under k. The result we read as lh.
We must now find a Premiss containing either l or h. Looking along the row, we fix on No. 2, and tack it on.
Now these 3 Nullities are really equivalent to (lh † dh), in which h and h must be eliminated, and what remains taken as one expression. So we underscore them. The result reads as ld.
We now want a Premiss containing l or d. No. 6 will do.
These 4 Nullities are really equivalent to (ld † bl). So we underscore l and l. The result reads as db.
We now want a Premiss containing d or b. No. 4 will do.
Here we underscore b and b. The result reads as de.
We now want a Premiss containing d or e. No. 7 will do.
Here we underscore d and d. The result reads as ce.
We now want a Premiss containing c or e. No. 3 will do—in fact must do, as it is the only one left.
Here we underscore c and c; and, as the whole thing now reads as ea, we tack on ea0 as the Conclusion, with a ¶.
We now look along the row of Data, to see whether e or a has been given as existent. We find that a has been so given in No. 3. So we add this fact to the Conclusion, which now stands as ¶ ea0 † a1, i.e. ¶ a1e0; i.e. “All a are e.”
If the Reader has faithfully obeyed the above directions, his written solution will now stand as follows:—
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg092
87/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
1 2 3 4 56 7 k1l0 † dh0 † a1c0 † b1e0 † kh0 † bl0 † d1c0
15 264 7 3 kl † kh † dh † bl † be † dc † ac ¶ ea0 † a1 i.e. ¶ a1e0;
i.e. “All a are e.”
The Reader should now take a second piece of paper, and copy the Data only, and try to work out the solution for himself, beginning with some other Premiss.
pg093
If he fails to bring out the Conclusion a1e0, I would advise him to take a third piece of paper, and begin again!]
I will now work out, in its briefest form, a Sorites of 5 Premisses, to serve as a model for the Reader to imitate in working examples.
(1) ”I greatly value everything that John gives me; (2) Nothing but this bone will satisfy my dog; (3) I take particular care of everything that I greatly value; (4) This bone was a present from John; (5) The things, of which I take particular care, are things I do not give to my dog”.
Univ. “things”; a = given by John to me; b = given by me to my dog; c = greatly valued by me; d = satisfactory to my dog; e = taken particular care of by me; h = this bone.
123 4 5 a1c0 † hd0 † c1e0 † h1a0 † e1b0
134 25 ac † ce † ha † hd † eb ¶ db0
i.e. “Nothing, that I give my dog, satisfies him,” or, “My dog is not satisfied with anything that I give him!”
[Note that, in working a Sorites by this process, we may begin with any Premiss we choose. For instance, we might begin with No. 5, and the result would then be
531 4 2 eb † ce † ac † ha † hd ¶ bd0]
[Work Examples § 4, 2530 (p. 100); § 5, 2530 (p. 102); § 6, 1315 (p. 106); § 7, 1315 (p. 108); § 8, 14, 13, 14, 19, 24 (pp. 110, 111); § 9, 14, 26, 27, 40, 48 (pp. 112, 116, 119, 121).]
The Reader, who has successfully grappled with all the Examples hitherto set, and who thirsts, like Alexander the Great, for “more worlds to conquer,” may employ his spare energies on the following 17 Examination-Papers. He is recommended not to attempt more than one Paper on any one day. The answers to the questions about words and phrases may be found by referring to the Index at p. 197.
pg094
I. § 4, 31 (p. 100); § 5, 3134 (p. 102); § 6, 16, 17 (p. 106); § 7, 16 (p. 108); § 8, 5, 6 (p. 110); § 9, 5, 22, 42 (pp. 112, 115, 119). What is Classification? And what is a Class?
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
88/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
II. § 4, 32 (p. 100); § 5, 3538 (pp. 102, 103); § 6, 18 (p. 107); § 7, 17, 18 (p. 108); § 8, 7, 8 (p. 110); § 9, 6, 23, 43 (pp. 112, 115, 119). What are Genus, Species, and Differentia?
III. § 4, 33 (p. 100); § 5, 3942 (p. 103); § 6, 19, 20 (p. 107); § 7, 19 (p. 109); § 8, 9, 10 (p. 111); § 9, 7, 24, 44 (pp. 113, 116, 120). What are Real and Imaginary Classes?
IV. § 4, 34 (p. 100); § 5, 4346 (p. 103); § 6, 21 (p. 107); § 7, 20, 21 (p. 109); § 8, 11, 12 (p. 111); § 9, 8, 25, 45 (pp. 113, 116, 120). What is Division? When are Classes said to be Codivisional?
V. § 4, 35 (p. 100); § 5, 4750 (p. 103); § 6, 22, 23 (p. 107); § 7, 22 (p. 109); § 8, 15, 16 (p. 111); § 9, 9, 28, 46 (pp. 113, 116, 120). What is Dichotomy? What arbitrary rule does it sometimes require?
VI. § 4, 36 (p. 100); § 5, 5154 (p. 103); § 6, 24 (p. 107); § 7, 23, 24 (p. 109); § 8, 17 (p. 111); § 9, 10, 29, 47 (pp. 113, 117, 120). What is a Definition?
VII. § 4, 37 (p. 100); § 5, 5558 (pp. 103, 104); § 6, 25, 26 (p. 107); § 7, 25 (p. 109); § 8, 18 (p. 111); § 9, 11, 30, 49 (pp. 113, 117, 121). What are the Subject and the Predicate of a Proposition? What is its Normal form?
VIII. § 4, 38 (p. 100); § 5, 5962 (p. 104); § 6, 27 (p. 107); § 7, 26, 27 (p. 109); § 8, 20 (p. 111); § 9, 12, 31, 50 (pp. 113, 117, 121). What is a Proposition in I? In E? And in A?
IX. § 4, 39 (p. 100); § 5, 6366 (p. 104); § 6, 28, 29 (p. 107); § 7, 28 (p. 109); § 8, 21 (p. 111); § 9, 13, 32, 51 (pp. 114, 117, 121). What is the Normal form of a Proposition of Existence?
X. § 4, 40 (p. 100); § 5, 6770 (p. 104); § 6, 30 (p. 107); § 7, 29, 30 (p. 109); § 8, 22 (p. 111); § 9, 14, 33, 52 (pp. 114, 117, 122). What is the Universe of Discourse?
XI. § 4, 41 (p. 100); § 5, 7174 (p. 104); § 6, 31, 32 (p. 107); § 7, 31 (p. 109); § 8, 23 (p. 111); § 9, 15, 34, 53 (pp. 114, 118, 122). What is implied, in a Proposition of Relation, as to the Reality of its Terms?
XII. § 4, 42 (p. 100); § 5, 7578 (p. 105); § 6, 33 (p. 107); § 7, 32, 33 (pp. 109, 110); § 8, 25 (p. 111); § 9, 16, 35, 54 (pp. 114, 118, 122). Explain the phrase “sitting on the fence”.
XIII.§ 5, 7983 (p. 105); § 6, 34, 35 (p. 107); § 7, 34 (p. 110); § 8, 26 (p. 111); § 9, 17, 36, 55 (pp. 114, 118, 122). What are Converse Propositions?
XIV. § 5, 8488 (p. 105); § 6, 36 (p. 107); § 7, 35, 36 (p. 110); § 8, 27 (p. 111); § 9, 18, 37, 56 (pp. 114, 118, 123). What are Concrete and Abstract Propositions?
XV. § 5, 8993 (p. 105); § 6, 37, 38 (p. 107); § 7, 37 (p. 110); § 8, 28 (p. 111); § 9, 19, 38, 57 (pp. 115, 118, 123). What is a Syllogism? And what are its Premisses and its Conclusion?
XVI.§ 5, 9497 (p. 106); § 6, 39 (p. 107); § 7, 38, 39 (p. 110); § 8, 29 (p. 111); § 9, 20, 39, 58 (pp. 115, 119, 123). What is a Sorites? And what are its Premisses, its Partial Conclusions, and its Complete Conclusion?
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg095
pg096
89/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
XVII.§ 5, 98101 (p. 106); § 6, 40 (p. 107); § 7, 40 (p. 110); § 8, 30 (p. 111); § 9, 21, 41, 59, 60 (pp. 115, 119, 124). What are the Universe of Discourse, the Eliminands, and the Retinends, of a Syllogism? And of a Sorites?
BOOK VIII.
EXAMPLES, ANSWERS, AND SOLUTIONS. [N.B. Reference tags for Examples, Answers & Solutions will be found in the right margin.]
CHAPTER I. EXAMPLES.
§ 1. Propositions of Relation, to be reduced to normal form. 1. I have been out for a walk. 2. I am feeling better. 3. No one has read the letter but John. 4. Neither you nor I are old. 5. No fat creatures run well. 6. None but the brave deserve the fair. 7. No one looks poetical unless he is pale. 8. Some judges lose their tempers. 9. I never neglect important business. 10. What is difficult needs attention. 11. What is unwholesome should be avoided. 12. All the laws passed last week relate to excise. 13. Logic puzzles me. 14. There are no Jews in the house. 15. Some dishes are unwholesome if not well-cooked. 16. Unexciting books make one drowsy. 17. When a man knows what hes about, he can detect a sharper. 18. You and I know what were about.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg097 EX1
90/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
19. Some bald people wear wigs.
Symbolic Logic
20. Those who are fully occupied never talk about their grievances.
21. No riddles interest me if they can be solved.
§ 2.
Pairs of Abstract Propositions, one in terms of x and m, and the other in terms of y and m, to be represented on the same Triliteral Diagram.
1. No x are m; No m are y.
pg098 EX2
2. No x are m; All m are y.
3. Some x are m; No m are y.
4. All m are x; All m are y.
5. All m are x; All m are y.
6. All x are m; No y are m.
7. All x are m; All y are m.
8. Some m are x; No m are y.
9. All m are x; No m are y.
10. No m are x; No y are m.
11. No x are m; No m are y.
12. Some x are m; All y are m.
13. All x are m; No m are y.
14. Some x are m; All m are y.
15. No m are x; All y are m.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
91/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
16. All x are m; No y are m.
17. Some m are x; No m are y.
18. All x are m; Some m are y.
19. All m are x; Some m are y.
20. No x are m; Some y are m.
21. Some x are m; All y are m.
22. No m are x; Some m are y.
23. No m are x; All y are m.
24. All m are x; No y are m.
25. Some m are x; No y are m.
26. All m are x; Some y are m.
27. Some m are x; No y are m.
28. No x are m; All m are y.
29. No x are m; No m are y.
30. No x are m; Some y are m.
31. Some m are x; All y are m;
32. All x are m; All y are m.
Symbolic Logic
§ 3.
Marked Triliteral Diagrams, to be interpreted in terms of x and y.
1
2
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg099 EX3
92/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
93/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
94/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
Symbolic Logic
19
20
§ 4.
Pairs of Abstract Propositions, proposed as Premisses: Conclusions to be found. 1. No m are x;
All m are y.
2. No m are x; Some m are y.
3. All m are x; All m are y.
4. No x are m; All y are m.
5. Some m are x; No y are m.
6. No x are m; No m are y.
7. No m are x; Some y are m.
8. All m are x; No m are y.
9. Some x are m; No m are y.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg100 EX4
95/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
10. All x are m; All y are m.
11. No m are x; All y are m.
12. No x are m; All y are m.
13. All m are x; No y are m.
14. All m are x; All m are y.
15. No x are m; No m are y.
16. All x are m; All y are m.
17. No x are m; All m are y.
18. No x are m; No m are y.
19. All m are x; All m are y.
20. No m are x; All m are y.
21. All x are m; Some m are y.
22. Some x are m; All y are m.
23. All m are x; Some y are m.
24. No x are m; All y are m.
25. Some m are x; All y are m.
26. No m are x; All y are m.
27. All x are m; All y are m.
28. All m are x; Some m are y.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
Symbolic Logic
96/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
29. No m are x; All y are m.
30. All x are m; Some y are m.
31. All x are m; All y are m.
32. No x are m; All m are y.
33. No m are x; No m are y.
34. No m are x; Some y are m.
35. No m are x; All y are m.
36. All m are x; Some y are m.
37. All m are x; No y are m.
38. No m are x; No m are y.
39. Some m are x; No m are y.
40. No x are m; All y are m.
41. All x are m; No y are m.
42. No m are x; No y are m.
Symbolic Logic
§ 5.
Pairs of Concrete Propositions, proposed as Premisses: Conclusions to be found. 1. I have been out for a walk;
I am feeling better.
2. No one has read the letter but John; No one, who has not read it, knows what it is about.
3. Those who are not old like walking; You and I are young.
pg101 EX5
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
97/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
4. Your course is always honest; Your course is always the best policy.
Symbolic Logic
5. No fat creatures run well; Some greyhounds run well.
6. Some, who deserve the fair, get their deserts; None but the brave deserve the fair.
7. Some Jews are rich; All Esquimaux are Gentiles.
8. Sugar-plums are sweet; Some sweet things are liked by children.
9. John is in the house; Everybody in the house is ill.
10. Umbrellas are useful on a journey; What is useless on a journey should be left behind.
11. Audible music causes vibration in the air; Inaudible music is not worth paying for.
12. Some holidays are rainy; Rainy days are tiresome.
13. No Frenchmen like plumpudding; All Englishmen like plumpudding.
14. No portrait of a lady, that makes her simper or scowl, is satisfactory; No photograph of a lady ever fails to make her simper or scowl.
15. All pale people are phlegmatic; No one looks poetical unless he is pale.
16. No old misers are cheerful; Some old misers are thin.
17. No one, who exercises self-control, fails to keep his temper; Some judges lose their tempers.
18. All pigs are fat; Nothing that is fed on barley-water is fat.
19. All rabbits, that are not greedy, are black; No old rabbits are free from greediness.
20. Some pictures are not first attempts; No first attempts are really good.
21. I never neglect important business; Your business is unimportant.
22. Some lessons are difficult; What is difficult needs attention.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg102
98/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
23. All clever people are popular; All obliging people are popular.
Symbolic Logic
24. Thoughtless people do mischief; No thoughtful person forgets a promise.
25. Pigs cannot fly; Pigs are greedy.
26. All soldiers march well; Some babies are not soldiers.
27. No bride-cakes are wholesome; What is unwholesome should be avoided.
28. John is industrious; No industrious people are unhappy.
29. No philosophers are conceited; Some conceited persons are not gamblers.
30. Some excise laws are unjust; All the laws passed last week relate to excise.
31. No military men write poetry; None of my lodgers are civilians.
32. No medicine is nice; Senna is a medicine.
33. Some circulars are not read with pleasure; No begging-letters are read with pleasure.
34. All Britons are brave; No sailors are cowards.
35. Nothing intelligible ever puzzles me; Logic puzzles me.
36. Some pigs are wild; All pigs are fat.
37. All wasps are unfriendly; All unfriendly creatures are unwelcome.
38. No old rabbits are greedy; All black rabbits are greedy.
39. Some eggs are hard-boiled; No eggs are uncrackable.
40. No antelope is ungraceful; Graceful creatures delight the eye.
41. All well-fed canaries sing loud; No canary is melancholy if it sings loud.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg103
99/223
9/4/23, 5:01 PM
42. Some poetry is original; No original work is producible at will.
Symbolic Logic
43. No country, that has been explored, is infested by dragons; Unexplored countries are fascinating.
44. No coals are white; No niggers are white.
45. No bridges are made of sugar; Some bridges are picturesque.
46. No children are patient; No impatient person can sit still.
47. No quadrupeds can whistle; Some cats are quadrupeds.
48. Bores are terrible; You are a bore.
49. Some oysters are silent; No silent creatures are amusing.
50. There are no Jews in the house; No Gentiles have beards a yard long.
51. Canaries, that do not sing loud, are unhappy; No well-fed canaries fail to sing loud.
52. All my sisters have colds; No one can sing who has a cold.
53. All that is made of gold is precious; Some caskets are precious.
54. Some buns are rich; All buns are nice.
55. All my cousins are unjust; All judges are just.
56. Pain is wearisome; No pain is eagerly wished for.
57. All medicine is nasty; Senna is a medicine.
58. Some unkind remarks are annoying; No critical remarks are kind.
59. No tall men have woolly hair; Niggers have woolly hair.
60. All philosophers are logical; An illogical man is always obstinate.
https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/28696/pg28696-images.html
pg104
100/223